Docsity
Docsity

Prepare for your exams
Prepare for your exams

Study with the several resources on Docsity


Earn points to download
Earn points to download

Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan


Guidelines and tips
Guidelines and tips

Evolutionary Developmental Biology, Schemes and Mind Maps of Developmental biology

Embryology played an indispensable role in the first inceptions of evolutionary theory by Charles. DARWIN, August WEISSMAN, Ernst HAECKEL, ...

Typology: Schemes and Mind Maps

2022/2023

Uploaded on 05/11/2023

johnatan
johnatan 🇺🇸

4

(27)

29 documents

1 / 13

Toggle sidebar

Related documents


Partial preview of the text

Download Evolutionary Developmental Biology and more Schemes and Mind Maps Developmental biology in PDF only on Docsity! ALTENBERG SEMINARS IN THEORETICAL BIOLOGY Summer 2006: Evolutionary Developmental Biology Hörsaal 1, Biozentrum, Althanstrasse 14, at 6.15 p.m. The Program at a glance: 9 March 2006 Stuart A. NEWMAN (New York Medical College, Valhalla, NY, USA): "Physical Determinants of Metazoan Form and the Molecular Homology-Analogy Paradox" 27 April 2006 Adam S. WILKINS (Editor, BioEssays, Cambridge): "Evolutionary Genetics, Genomics, Genetic Networks: How Should We Approach the Genetic Foundations of the Evolution of Development/Morphology?" 1 June 2006 Frietson GALIS (Leiden University): "The Evolutionary Conservation of Body Plans: Internal Selection, Pleiotropy, and Homeobox Genes" 22 June 2006 James R. GRIESEMER (University of California, Davis): "Variational Models for Developmental Processes: A New Ontology for Evo-Devo" 29 June 2006 Rudolf A. RAFF (Indiana University Bloomington, USA): "Mechanisms of Radical Evolutionary Changes in Larval Morphology" The topic Embryology played an indispensable role in the first inceptions of evolutionary theory by Charles DARWIN, August WEISSMAN, Ernst HAECKEL, and others. Yet embryology — which more recently came to be called developmental biology — was conspicuously absent from the Modern or Evolutionary Synthesis. Evolutionary biology was built on a huge black box; and maybe, as is sometimes suggested, rightly so: " DARWIN could never have written the Origin of Species if he had not wisely bracketed the mechanism of inheritance" (AMUNDSON 1994). Similarly, it is often seen as a great advantage of Mendelian genetics in the early decades of the 20th century that it "bypassed the uncharted swamp of development" (David HULL). The disrepute of Haeckelian recapitulationism as well as neo-Lamarckian beliefs about environmental influences on embryogenesis, which many developmentalists continued to advocate, contributed to this ostracism. In the past two decades or so developmental considerations have come to the fore again, stimulated by the rise of molecular developmental genetics (RAFF 1996; HALL 1999; DAVIDSON 2001; GILBERT 2003; CARROLL ET AL. 2004), and motivated by a number of explanatory deficits in the prevailing evolutionary paradigm. The field that embraces studies of embryonic development as the vehicle for evolutionary change is called evolutionary developmental biology ("EDB" or "EvoDevo"). EvoDevo forges a synthesis of mechanisms that operate during ontogeny with those that operate during phylogeny (between generations). Brian K. HALL (2000) characterizes EvoDevo as a way of integrating proximate and ultimate causes for the origin of phenotypes. As the empirical and theoretical analysis of the causal-mechanical connection between embryological/developmental and evolutionary processes, EvoDevo is immanently dialectical: on one hand, it is interested in the factors that together explain the "origination" of ontogenetic systems and the mechanisms that account for their subsequent modification, suppression, or loss (MÜLLER and NEWMAN 2003); on the other, it investigates the ways in which the properties of ontogenetic processes influence the course of morphological evolution (cf. GILBERT ET AL. 1996; RAFF 2000). Concepts that help delineate EvoDevo from more established research in developmental biology and evolutionary biology include body plans, combinations of morphological characters of a taxon that have been unusually conserved during evolution (GALIS seminar); canalization, the reduced sensitivity of a phenotype to changes or perturbations in the underlying genetic and nongenetic factors that determine its expression; constraints, processes or mechanisms that limit the ability of the phenotype to evolve or bias it along certain paths (GALIS seminar; cf. AMUNDSON 1984); evolvability, the inherent potential of certain lineages to change during the course of evolution; and modularity, which views organisms as the integration of partially independent, interacting units at several hierarchical levels (RAFF seminar). Three concepts that we take to be pivotal for EvoDevo — evolutionary origination, innovation, and novelty — will be highlighted in particular in NEWMAN's seminar. Comparative developmental biology, experimental developmental biology, and evolutionary developmental genetics are the methods most commonly relied on in EvoDevo. From an epistemological point of view, what current EvoDevo seems to be largely lacking is a way to get from the knowledge of parts (entities and their properties) and what they do to each other — "local knowledge" that developmental genetics increasingly provides — to a full-fledged, formal explanation of developmental phenomena. Developmental genetics begins with an induced anomaly (a mutation) and a (hopefully discrete) consequence, then proceeds to decipher a "perturbation-to-consequence chain" — a kind of account that "doesn't articulate any sense of the mapping from genotype to phenotype, which is what we ultimately want" (VON DASSOW and MUNRO 1999). COFFMAN (2006) proposes that during immature stages with relatively low specification and high potential, development is largely controlled by local interactions from the "bottom-up," whereas during more highly specified stages with reduced potential, emergent autocatalytic processes exert "top-down" control ("developmental ascendency"). The explanatory strategy Stuart NEWMAN will explore in his seminar focuses on the epigenetic factors that are causal in the evolution and organization of phenotypes. Here the generic physical properties of cells and tissue masses and their self-organizational properties are given priority over the molecules that are used in these processes. His picture implies two evolutionary regimes in the history Biographical note Stuart A. NEWMAN (AB 1965, Columbia, PhD chemistry, 1970, University of Chicago) is a professor of Cell Biology and Anatomy at New York Medical College, Valhalla, NY. He has contributed to several scientific fields, including biophysical chemistry, developmental biology, and evolutionary theory. He has held faculty positions at the State University of New York at Albany and the University of Pennsylvania, and was a visiting research fellow at the University of Sussex, UK, an INSERM Fellow at the Pasteur Institute, Paris, a Fogarty Senior International Fellow at Monash University, Australia, and a visiting scientist at the University of Paris-Sud, the French Atomic Energy Center- Saclay, the Indian Institute of Science, Bangalore, the KLI, and the University of Tokyo. Dr. NEWMAN was a founding member of the Council for Responsible Genetics (Cambridge, MA) and is currently a Fellow of the Institute on Biotechnology and the Human Future (Chicago, IL). Selected publications (2006) The developmental-genetic toolkit and the molecular homology-analogy paradox. Biological Theory 1, in press. (2005) Biological Physics of the Developing Embryo (with G FORGACS). Cambridge UP. (2004) Dynamical mechanisms for skeletal pattern formation in the vertebrate limb (with HGE HENTSCHEL, T GLIMM, and JA GLAZIER). Proceedings of the Royal Society London B271: 1713—1722. (2003) Origination of Organismal Form: Beyond the Gene in Developmental and Evolutionary Biology (ed, with GB MÜLLER). MIT Press. (2003) Mechanisms of pattern formation in development and evolution (with I SALAZAR-CIUDAD and J JERNVALL). Development 130: 2027—2037. (2000) Epigenetic mechanisms of character origination (with GB MÜLLER). Journal of Experimental Zoology B 288: 304—317. (1994) Generic physical mechanisms of tissue morphogenesis: A common basis for development and evolution. Journal of Evolutionary Biology 7: 467—488. (1990) 'Generic' physical mechanisms of morphogenesis and pattern formation (with WD COMPER). Development 110: 1—18. Adam S. WILKINS Editor, BioEssays Evolutionary Genetics, Genomics, Genetic Networks: How Should We Approach the Genetic Foundations of the Evolution of Development/Morphology? 27 April 2006 Abstract The goals of EvoDevo as a field are to understand the mechanisms, processes, and patterns of evolutionary change in developmental change, which have been responsible for the immense diversity of animal and plant forms that have arisen on Earth during the past 550 million years. Successful completion of the “task” of the field, however, will depend, in part, on advances in understanding in developmental biology itself, in particular of the processes of morphogenesis and how these processes relate to their underlying informational (genetic) foundations. Within the domain of EvoDevo itself, however, lies another distinct challenge — understanding the nature of the genetic changes that are intrinsic to the changing patterns of form – shape, size, and color patterns — that constitute the diverging morphological sequences in different lineages. Since a vast amount is known about mutational processes, in both formal genetic and detailed molecular terms, this might seem to be relatively easy to resolve. It is not, however, because there are, in reality, some strong divergences in viewpoint about the kinds of genetic change that are most important in developmental evolution. These different viewpoints are embodied in three distinct fields, with their own distinctive approaches: evolutionary genetics, genomics, and systems biology — the latter devoted to what can be called “network thinking.” In this talk, I will discuss these different approaches and their respective strengths and limitations. I will argue that “network thinking” is the critically important approach but that it, too, will be inadequate unless it incorporates key elements of the other approaches. A critical challenge for the field will be effecting that synthesis. In the penultimate part of the talk, I will discuss three evolutionary problems where the network perspective in itself deepens understanding of the issues — even in the absence of detailed knowledge of any specific genetic networks involved. And, in the final part, I will return to the ultimate and still most difficult task ahead, the needed synthesis between “physicalist” and informational (genetic) approaches if we are to understand morphogenesis and the evolution of morphogenetic processes. Biographical note Adam S. WILKINS has been the Editor of BioEssays, a review journal specializing in molecular, cellular and developmental biology (now published by Wiley) since January 1990, after having been the journal's Staff Editor at Cambridge UP from 1984 to 1989. Dr. WILKINS studied Biology at Reed College, Portland, Oregon (BA, 1965) and genetics at the University of Washington, Seattle (PhD, 1969). He held postdoc positions in MIT's Department of Biology (1969-1973), where he worked in phage molecular genetics, and in the McArdle Laboratory for Cancer Research, University of Wisconsin, Madison, where he was involved in research on slime mould genetics, cell biology, and developmental biology. Dr. WILKINS was a Lecturer and Senior Lecturer in Genetics at Massey University, Palmerston North, New Zealand (1976-1983), and a Visiting Professor in the departments of genetics at the University of Washington, WA (1985), and the University of Wisconsin, Madison (1987 and 1993). He also held a Visiting Lectureship at the Department of Biochemistry, The National University of Singapore (1994). Selected publications (2005). Recasting developmental evolution in terms of genetic pathway and network evolution and the implications for comparative biology. Brain Research Bulletin 66: 495—606. (2005). The molecular elements that underlie developmental evolution (with CR ALONSO). Nature Reviews Genetics 6: 709—715. (2004). Embryology: A discipline that has undergone dissolution through infiltration, redefinition and diffusion. Bulletin d'Histoire et d'Epistémologie des Sciences de la Vie 11: 219—233. (2004).The evolution of the Drosophila sex determination pathway (with A POMIANKOWSKI and R NOTHIGER). Genetics 166: 1761—1763. (2002) The Evolution of Developmental Pathways. Sinauer. (1998) The evolution of 'bricolage' (with D. DUBOULE). Trends in Genetics 14: 54—59. (1995) Molecular Model Systems in the Lepidoptera (ed, with M GOLDSMITH). Cambridge UP. (1986) Genetic Analysis of Animal Development. 2nd ed, 1993. Wiley. (1984) Molecular Evolution (ed, with EA TERZAGHI and D PENNY). Jones and Bartlett. James R. GRIESEMER Department of Philosophy University of California Variational Models for Developmental Processes: A New Ontology for Evo-Devo 22 June 2006 Abstract It is often argued that models of evolution describe changes in population-level variation due to processes such as natural selection while models of development concern transformational processes within individual organisms. I sketch a process perspective on the relations between reproduction and development that bridges this divide and suggest ways to characterize and model developmental processes that are integrative rather than reductionist, taking into account deep connections between heredity and development rather than explaining all developmental processes in terms of genetic units. Historical and contemporary examples from developmental biology and evolution illustrate the new process ontology in contrast to the traditional one based on a hierarchy of genetic units. Biographical note James R. GRIESEMER has been a Professor in the Department of Philosophy at the University of California, Davis since 1996. He holds an AB in Genetics from the University of California, Berkeley (1977), an MS in Biology from the University of Chicago (1981), and a PhD in Conceptual Foundations of Science from the University of Chicago (1983). He joined Davis in 1983 after having been a researcher at the Museum of Science and Industry in Chicago (1981). He is an affiliate of the Center for History and Philosophy of Science of the California Academy of Sciences, and has been a fellow at the Wissenschaftskolleg zu Berlin (1992-93), the Collegium Budapest/Institute for Advanced Studies (1994-95), and the Max Planck Institut für Wissenschaftsgeschichte in Berlin (1998). Selected publications (In press) Gánti’s chemoton model and life criteria (with E. SZATHMÁRY). In: Protocells: Bridging Nonliving and Living Matter (RASMUSSEN R et al. eds). MIT Press. (In press) Tracking organic processes: Representations and research styles in classical embryology and genetics. In: From Embryology to Evo-Devo (MAIENSCHEIN J, LAUBICHLER MD, eds.). MIT Press. (2006) Theoretical integration, cooperation, and theories as tracking devices. Biological Theory 1: 1— 4. (2006) Genetics from an evolutionary process perspective. In: Genes in Development (NEUMANN- HELD EM, REHMANN-SUTTER C, eds). Duke University Press. (2005) Cycles of contingency: Developmental systems and evolution (with M HABER, Y YAMASHITA, L GANNETT). Biology and Philosophy 20: 517–544. (2005) The informational gene and the substantial body: On the generalization of evolutionary theory by abstraction. In Idealization XII: Correcting the Model (JONES MR, CARTWRIGHT N, eds). Amsterdam: Rodopi. (2004) Classical genetics and the geography of genes (with L. GANNETT). In: Mapping Cultures of Twentieth Century Genetics (RHEINBERGER H-J, GAUDILLIERE J-P, eds.). Routledge. (2004) The ABO blood groups: Mapping the history and geography of genes in Homo sapiens (with L. GANNETT). In: Mapping Cultures of Twentieth Century Genetics (RHEINBERGER H-J, GAUDILLIERE J-P, eds.). Routledge. (2004) Three-dimensional models in philosophical perspective. In: Models: The Third Dimension of Science (DE CHADAREVIAN S, HOPWOOD N, eds). Stanford UP. (2003) The philosophical significance of Gánti's work. In: The Principles of Life, with a Commentary by James Griesemer and Eörs Szathmáry (GÁNTI T et al, eds). Oxford UP. (2002) What is "epi" about epigenetics? In: From Epigenesis to Epigenetics: the Genome in Context (VANDEVIJVER G et al., eds). Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 981: 97—110. (2002) Limits of reproduction: A reductionistic research strategy in evolutionary biology. In: Promises and Limits of Reductionism in the Biomedical Sciences (Van Regenmortel MHV, Hull DL, eds). Chichester: Wiley. (2002) Weismann, August Friederich Leopold (with FB CHURCHILL). In: Encyclopedia of Evolution, Vol. 2 (PAGEL M, ed). Oxford UP. (2000) The units of evolutionary transition. Selection 1: 67—80. (2000) Development, culture and the units of inheritance. Philosophy of Science 67: S348—S368. (2000) Reproduction and the reduction of genetics. In: The Concept of the Gene in Development and Evolution (BEURTON P et al., eds), 240—285. Cambridge UP. (2000) Populational heritability: Extending Punnett square concepts to evolution at the metapopulation level (with MJ WADE). Biology and Philosophy 15: 1—17. Rudolf A. RAFF Indiana Molecular Biology Institute Indiana University, Bloomington, USA Mechanisms of Radical Evolutionary Changes in Larval Morphology 29 June 2006 Abstract Despite the fact that all of the later stages of ontogeny of any animal are based on the events of embryonic and larval development, these early stages of development can evolve rapidly and dramatically among closely related forms. Larval development is relatively simple morphologically and in terms of gene regulation compared to adult development, which allows relatively rapid evolution to occur. In addition, the simpler larval systems lend themselves to more straightforward investigation. Basal sea urchin development is via a feeding pluteus larva. Direct development, in which feeding structures are lost and development to metamorphosis is accelerated, is derived. In Heliocidaris erythrogramma, direct development has evolved in less than 4 x 106 years since its divergence from H. tuberculata, which has a feeding pluteus. Although the H. erythrogramma larva appears simpler in form than the pluteus, it is in fact equally complex in process and structure. The evolution of direct development in H. erythrogramma involves a series of modifications to various processes in ontogeny, including oogenesis, cell fate specification, axis formation, and morphogenesis. These evolutionary changes are accessible to study experimentally at the level of gene action, and we have been able to demonstrate that at least one gene is responsible for a large effect on morphogenesis. Despite the enormous differences in ontogeny, it is possible to make viable cross species hybrids that have a novel ontogeny and yet metamorphose into sea urchins. The hybrids have allowed us to investigate gene interactions, and to focus on gene regulatory changes. We have found that evolution is faster in the H. erythrogramma lineage than in indirect developers. Evolution has largely involved changes in modular units. Most changes involve gene expression heterochronies, but there are module fusions, losses of localized gene expression patterns, gene losses, and gene co-options as well. Biographical note Rudolf A. RAFF is James H. Rudy Professor of Biology and Director of the Indiana Molecular Biology Institute, College of Arts and Sciences, University Graduate School, Indiana University, Bloomington. He served as a Navy lieutenant, was instructor-in-chief of the Summer Embryology Course at the Marine Biological Laboratory at Woods Hole, and founded the Indiana Molecular Biology Institute at Indiana University in 1983. Dr. RAFF is co-founder and editor-in-chief of the journal Evolution and Development and has served as an associate editor for several other journals; he is also a member of the editorial board of Biology and Philosophy. He has been invited to lecture widely — recently at the University of Chicago, Duke University, the University of Toronto, the Pasteur Institute in Paris, and a public lecture sponsored by the city of Aomori in Japan. Since 1986, he has been an annual visiting scholar at the University of Sydney, Australia. Awards that RAFF has received include fellowships from the National Institutes of Health, the American Cancer Society, and the Guggenheim Foundation. He won the 2001 Kowalevsky Medal and was elected to the American Academy of Arts and Sciences in 2000. Selected publications (2000) Modularity and dissociation in the evolution of gene expression territories in development (with BJ SLY). Evolution and Development 2: 102—113. (1999) A novel ontogenetic pathway in hybrid embryos between species with different modes of development (with EC RAFF, EM POPODI, BJ SLY, FR TURNER, and JT VILLINSKI). Development 126: 1937—1945.
Docsity logo



Copyright © 2024 Ladybird Srl - Via Leonardo da Vinci 16, 10126, Torino, Italy - VAT 10816460017 - All rights reserved