Docsity
Docsity

Prepare for your exams
Prepare for your exams

Study with the several resources on Docsity


Earn points to download
Earn points to download

Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan


Guidelines and tips
Guidelines and tips

FRAMING EFFECTS, Exams of Psychology

A “framing effect” is usually said to occur when equivalent descriptions of a decision problem lead to systematically different decisions. Framing has been a ...

Typology: Exams

2022/2023

Uploaded on 03/01/2023

fazal
fazal 🇺🇸

4.5

(11)

2 documents

1 / 9

Toggle sidebar

Related documents


Partial preview of the text

Download FRAMING EFFECTS and more Exams Psychology in PDF only on Docsity! FRAMING EFFECTS A “framing effect” is usually said to occur when equivalent descriptions of a decision problem lead to systematically different decisions. Framing has been a major topic of research in the psychology of judgment and decision making and is widely viewed as carrying significant implications for the “Rationality Debate” (e.g., Shafir and LeBoeuf 2002). Framing effects are commonly taken as evidence for incoherence in human decision making, and for the empirical inapplicability of the rational actor models used by economists and other social scientists. The first part of this entry presents a brief review of the empirical phenomena; the second part describes the standard normative interpretation of these empirical effects. Though the literature has not typically focused on the structure of human conversational environments, framing effects involve utterances selected by a “speaker” for a “listener”. A final section considers the possible implications of communicative factors for a normative and descriptive understanding of framing effects. Empirical Review In this section, we follow Levin, Schneider, and Gaeth’s (1998) taxonomy of framing effects into three categories: attribute framing, risky choice framing, and goal framing. In attribute framing, a single attribute of a single object is described in terms of either a positively valenced proportion or an equivalent negatively valenced proportion. The subject is then required to provide some evaluation of the object thus described. The typical finding is a valence-consistent shift (Levin et al., 1998): Objects described in terms of a positively valenced proportion are generally evaluated more favorably than objects described in terms of the corresponding negatively valenced proportion. For example, in one study, beef described as “75% lean” was given higher ratings than beef described as “25% fat” (Levin and Gaeth 1988); similarly, research and development (R&D) teams are allocated more funds when their performance rates are framed in terms of successes rather than failures (Duchon et al., 1989). The valence-consistent shift in attribute framing is a robust effect, observed in a large range of experimental environments, with obvious implications for marketing and persuasion. In risky choice framing, subjects are presented with two options in a forced- choice task. The two options are typically gambles which can be described in terms of proportions and probabilities of gains or losses. Usually, one of these options is a sure thing (in which an intermediate outcome is specified as certain), while the other is a risky gamble (in which extreme good and bad values are both assigned non-zero probabilities). The gamble and sure thing are both described either in terms of gain outcomes and probabilities or else in terms of equivalent loss outcomes and probabilities. The two options are usually equated in expected value (i.e., the mean outcome expected over many repeated trials), enabling the framing researcher to interpret observed patterns of preference in terms of subjects’ risk attitudes. Within this rubric, preferences for the sure thing indicate risk aversion and preferences for the gamble indicate risk seeking. The best-known risky choice framing problem is the so-called “Asian Disease Problem” (Tversky and Kahneman 1981). In it, subjects first read the following background blurb: the principle of description invariance states that it is also a normative requirement. Because the framing phenomena observed both in the laboratory and in real-world situations violate the description invariance principle, these effects are taken to imply that “no theory of choice can be both normatively adequate and descriptively accurate.” (Tversky and Kahneman 1986, S251) Framing, Communication, and Rational Norms Though framing effects are mainly investigated in relation to normative choice models, such effects are clearly bound up with human language, and closely related phenomena have been investigated by language scholars. For example, MARKEDNESS theorists have documented subtly different information conveyed by opposing polar adjectives. The school of COGNITIVE LINGUISTICS has drawn on a more general notion of frame in its treatment of fundamental issues in SEMANTICS (see FRAME SEMANTICS). “Framing”, in the broad sense, enters crucially into many processes of COMMUNICATION, and can only be fully understood in the context of those processes. Experimental framing effects involve utterances selected by “speakers” for “listeners”, but the standard normative analysis, described above, applies to listener effects without any consideration of associated speaker phenomena (i.e., regularities in how speakers choose frames in typical linguistic environments). Researchers have tended to interpret the experimental effects as if the experimenter had somehow surgically implanted a framing of the decision problem into the subject’s brain. However, because linguistic utterances are employed, regularities in speaker behavior may be relevant to the normative and descriptive understanding of listener behavior: If speakers tend to choose different frames as a function of background conditions, then listeners may reasonably draw inferences from the speaker’s choice of frame. If knowledge of these background conditions is relevant to the listener’s choice, then the frames, while logically equivalent, would not be information equivalent. Sher and McKenzie (2006; cf. McKenzie and Nelson 2003) argued that the frames studied in the attribute framing literature are commonly information non-equivalent, because speakers tend to frame options in terms of attributes that are relatively salient. For example, a generally impressive R&D team is more likely to be described in terms of its “success” rate than a generally incompetent team with the same success/failure rate. A positive frame thus highlights the salience of the positive attribute in the speaker’s conception of the option – information relevant to its evaluation. Experiments convey information to subjects in framed statements, and researchers have generally assumed that the only information content is logical information content. The framing of the logical content is assumed not to convey information, but simply to influence the listener’s construal of the logical content. In this way, the usual normative analysis of framing experiments leans on an implicit assumption of the information equivalence of logically equivalent frames. However, while the logical equivalence of a pair of frames can usually be determined on inspection (though see Jou et al. 1996), a determination of information equivalence requires empirical study of the human communicative environments in which speakers typically frame objects and options. At least in the domain of attribute framing, logical equivalence does not imply information equivalence. Whether the study of communicative environments will have similar implications for traditional normative conclusions drawn in risky choice and goal framing is an open question. There also remain important questions about how, and how flexibly, listeners use subtle information which is in principle available in particular framing experiments. However, an analysis of speaker regularities in human communicative environments is likely to be of some significance in any research area in which information presented to experimental subjects is evaluated against a normative standard of information equivalence (cf. Hilton 1995; McKenzie 2004; Sher and McKenzie, forthcoming; Schwarz 1996). – Shlomi Sher and Craig R. M. McKenzie Works Cited and Suggestions for Further Reading Duchon, D., K. J. Dunegan, & S. L. Barton. 1989. “Framing the Problem and Making Decisions: The Facts are Not Enough.” IEEE Transactions on Engineering Management, February: 25-27. Hilton, D. J. 1995. “The Social Context of Reasoning: Conversational Inference and Rational Judgment.” Psychological Bulletin 118: 248-271. Jou, J., J. Shanteau, & R. J. Harris. 1996. “An Information Processing View of Framing Effects: The Role of Causal Schemas in Decision Making.” Memory & Cognition 24: 1- 15. Kahneman, D. 2000. “Preface.” In Choices, Values, and Frames, ed. Kahneman and Tversky. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kahneman, D. & A. Tversky. 1979. “Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under Risk.” Econometrica 47: 263-91. Levin, I. P., & G. J. Gaeth. 1988. “How Consumers are Affected by the Framing of Attribute Information Before and After Consuming the Product.” Journal of Consumer Research 15: 374-378.
Docsity logo



Copyright © 2024 Ladybird Srl - Via Leonardo da Vinci 16, 10126, Torino, Italy - VAT 10816460017 - All rights reserved