Docsity
Docsity

Prepare for your exams
Prepare for your exams

Study with the several resources on Docsity


Earn points to download
Earn points to download

Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan


Guidelines and tips
Guidelines and tips

Hume's Theory of Knowable Relations: Constituting Sensory Knowledge, Study notes of Philosophy of mind

Hume's theory of knowable relations, focusing on sections 1.3.1 and 1.3.2 from his Treatise. Hume argues that knowable relations are the metaphysically necessary relations, and he uses the Conceivability Principle to identify them. The document also discusses Hume's standards for knowledge and the distinction between knowable and probability relations. Hume's account of knowledge, the Constitutive Account, makes room for sensory knowledge constituted by impressions.

Typology: Study notes

2021/2022

Uploaded on 03/31/2022

torley
torley 🇺🇸

4.5

(35)

21 documents

1 / 46

Toggle sidebar

Related documents


Partial preview of the text

Download Hume's Theory of Knowable Relations: Constituting Sensory Knowledge and more Study notes Philosophy of mind in PDF only on Docsity! Knowledge and Sensory Knowledge in Hume’s Treatise forthcoming in Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy (penultimate draft; please cite published version) Graham Clay If we carry our enquiry beyond the appearances of objects to the senses, I am afraid, that most of our conclusions will be full of scepticism and uncertainty. (T 1.2.5.26n12.2App) 1 1. INTRODUCTION Despite the wealth of attention paid to Hume’s empiricism, there is little dedicated to his views on the relationship between sense perception and knowledge. This gap in the literature is owed, in no small part, to a broader issue: namely that Hume’s positive views on knowledge do not feature prominently in his writings. Commentators are focused on what Hume is focused on. In this paper, I will argue that Hume’s A Treatise of Human Nature makes clear that he holds that there is sensory knowledge. Specifically, I will argue that Hume holds that there are relations of impressions that both constitute sensory knowledge and are its objects. All one needs to do is sense and, if the objects of one’s senses are of the right sort, one thereby knows. For example, when I see that two patches of red in my immediate visual field resemble one another, I thereby know that they do. Or, at least, so Hume would maintain. While there is direct textual evidence for these interpretative claims, it requires contextualization. To that end, I will first argue for an interpretation of Hume’s positive position on knowledge that is appropriately situated relative to his broader system. I will argue that Hume’s position has three components: (i) every instance of knowledge must be an immediately present perception (i.e., an impression or an idea); (ii) an object of this perception must be a token of a knowable relation; 2 and (iii) this token knowable relation must have parts of the instance of knowledge as relata (i.e., the same perception that has it as an object). I call the conjunction of these three claims and the further claim that any perception that satisfies them is an instance of knowledge the Constitutive Account. Given Hume’s relatively sparse positive claims about knowledge, establishing that the Constitutive Account is his view is no easy task, and it will occupy much of my attention in what follows. After giving my case for attributing the Constitutive Account to Hume in section 2, I will defend my interpretation against an alternative and several objections in section 3. This discussion also serves to locate the Constitutive Account relative to Hume’s other commitments. In section 4, with the help of some important passages from the Treatise, I will apply the Constitutive Account to sense perception in order to argue that Hume holds that there is sensory knowledge. Given what has come before, this means that, on my interpretation, Hume holds that some impressions are instances of knowledge because they have tokens of the knowable relations as both parts and objects. 2. HUMEAN KNOWLEDGE: ITS OBJECTS, STANDARDS, AND NATURE The texts where Hume expounds upon his positive views on knowledge are few and far between. They amount to a series of glimpses of an underlying picture that Hume never fully reveals. They consist of one small section of the Treatise explicitly dedicated to the topic (section 1.3.1; ‘Of knowledge’); the subsequent section, which finds Hume briefly discussing sense perception and its connection with knowledge; and a smattering of other passages throughout the rest of his corpus. 2 My focus will be on these two sections—T 1.3.1 and T 1.3.2— since Hume indicates that they are where his positive account is to be found. These two sections provide sufficient evidence to attribute the Constitutive Account to Hume. 5 causation. Two objects, tho’ perfectly resembling each other, and even appearing in the same place at different times, may be numerically different: And as the power, by which one object produces another, is never discoverable merely from their ideas, ‘tis evident cause and effect are relations, of which we receive information from experience, and not from any abstract reasoning or reflection. There is no single phænomenon, even the most simple, which can be accounted for from the qualities of the objects, as they appear to us; or which we cou’d foresee without the help of our memory and experience. (T 1.3.1.1) So long as we have two things in mind, we can ‘discover’ whether a knowable relation holds of them or not—no other information needed. Having the intrinsic properties of the relata in mind is sufficient because the relations hold in virtue of them alone. By contrast, we cannot foresee whether probability relations hold ‘without the help of our memory and experience’ of other facts. This is because the intrinsic nature of the relata of probability relations does not determine whether the relations hold or not. The reason that Hume justifies the condition undergirding the distinction between the two classes of relations in this way is that he holds that we must be able to determine ‘without any possibility of error’ (T 1.3.1.5) whether or not two beings bear a relation to one another, if we are to know whether or not they do. There must no possibility that a knower is in error about what she knows. Hume repeatedly indicates that this is his underlying view when he uses the term ‘infallible’ in connection with knowledge and when he uses ‘certainty’ interchangeably with ‘knowledge’. 12 Hume expresses the same view in different terms when he indicates that knowledge is a form of scientia, which is a variety of knowledge that Descartes and other predecessors held to be maximally epistemically certain. 13 As Frederick Schmitt argues, by all 6 indications, Hume’s view is that the relevant sort of certainty just is ‘infallibility or the impossibility of error.’ 14 If a relation’s holding depends on its extrinsic properties, then one could have its relata in mind and yet still be wrong about whether it holds or not. One must rely on one’s fallible ‘memory and experience’ in determining whether a probability relation holds or not. By contrast, for a relation to qualify as a knowable relation, it must be ‘discoverable’ from the perceptions of the relata alone, in the sense that if one has the intrinsic properties of the relata in mind, then one cannot be mistaken about whether the relata bear the relation to one another. The rest of the world need not cooperate. Thus, the aforementioned condition undergirds the distinction between the knowable and probability relations because Hume maintains that one has knowledge of something only if one cannot err about it being as one thinks it is. In this fashion, Hume’s justification of the condition that filters the knowable relations from the rest reveals his standards for knowledge. 15 Hume holds that the knowable relations are also the metaphysically necessary relations. 16 Hume identifies the relations that are discoverable a priori with the necessary relations because of his endorsement of the Conceivability Principle, which is the claim that ‘whatever we conceive is possible’ (T 1.4.5.10). 17 Hume argues that, for any two things and for any given probability relation, we can conceive either that they bear the relation to one another or that they do not. 18 Given the Conceivability Principle, it follows that it is possible for the probability relations to hold or to fail to hold between any two things. 19 Seeing as Hume holds that one must be certain about whether a relation holds or not if one is to know it, and this certainty is attainable only if one is aware of the intrinsic properties of its relata, it follows that, for Hume, candidates for knowledge must provide certain awareness 7 about what the intrinsic properties of the relata are, and they must do so at the time that one knows the relation. It is not enough for one to be certain that, were a given pair of things to have so-and-so intrinsic properties at some time, then, simply in virtue of these properties, a relation would hold or not between the things at that time. There must be no room for errors of misrepresentation. The only things in Hume’s system that he holds we cannot misrepresent are those that are ‘immediately present’ to the mind. Anything that is distinct from one’s representations of it could be misrepresented, but there is no such gap with immediately present things. As a consequence, if one is to know a relation, then the intrinsic properties of its relata must be immediately present to the knower at the time that they are known. Since Hume holds that one’s perceptions are the only things that can be immediately present, they are the only things that have intrinsic properties that can be immediately present. 20 Hume explicitly relies on the former view when he argues that we are reduced to making inferences about things that are not perceptions on the basis of the probability relation of cause and effect: The only existences, of which we are certain, are perceptions, which being immediately present to us by consciousness, command our strongest assent, and are the first foundation of all our conclusions. The only conclusion we can draw from the existence of one thing to that of another, is by means of the relation of cause and effect, which shows, that there is a connexion betwixt them, and that the existence of one is dependent on that of the other. The idea of this relation is deriv’d from past experience, by which we find, that two beings are constantly conjoin’d together, and are always present at once to the mind. But as no beings are ever present to the mind but perceptions; it follows that we 10 immediately present perception that is an instance of knowledge is the very same perception that has, as parts, the relata of the knowable relation that it has as an object. 26 The preceding argumentation does not rule out the possibility that a knower’s instance of knowledge is distinct from but co-occurrent with what she knows (the object of her instance of knowledge). Suppose, for purposes of a reductio, that Hume were to hold that it is not the case that every instance of knowledge k must be the very same immediately present perception whose parts are the relata of the token knowable relation that k has as an object. It follows that Hume would hold that it is possible that there is some instance of knowledge that is distinct from its object. Whether such an instance of knowledge is either another perception or something else entirely, Hume would hold that it would be conceivable that it exists and its object does not. After all, Hume endorses both the Separability Principle and the Conceivability Principle. The Separability Principle is the view that ‘whatever objects are different are distinguishable, and that whatever objects are distinguishable are separable by the thought and imagination’ (T 1.1.7.3). For any two numerically distinct things, one can conceive of them as separate—it is conceivable that one exists and the other does not. 27 Given the Conceivability Principle, it follows that it would be possible that one exists and the other does not (and vice versa). Therefore, if there were some instance of knowledge k that was distinct from its object, then it would be possible that k exists but it is not the case that its object exists. But if this were possible, then it would be possible that a knower could be in error about whether the known—a token knowable relation— holds or not. 28 Since Hume denies that the latter is possible because a knower must be certain about what she knows, it follows that Hume must hold that every instance of knowledge k is the very same immediately present perception whose parts are the relata of the token knowable relation that k has as an object. 29 11 Consider the case of an idea of the resemblance holding between a patch of crimson and a patch of scarlet. If one is to know this resemblance, on Hume’s view, it must be a relation between the parts of the very idea one has of it. If the patches were distinct from the idea, then their resemblance could fail to exist when the idea exists. It would be an error to have an idea of them resembling when it is not the case that they resemble. Since knowing precludes any possibility of erring, such an idea would not be an instance of knowledge. Although my arguments for both parts of (iii) are derived from T 1.3.1 and Hume’s principles (which are independently supported by the texts), they are also directly supported by the texts. Hume’s endorsement of these components of the Constitutive Account is the best explanation of his assertions in T 1.3.1.1 that knowable relations ‘depend entirely on the ideas’, that they remain ‘invariable, as long as our idea remains the same’, and that they are ‘discoverable merely from their ideas’. Hume makes similar claims elsewhere, as in T 1.3.3.2: ‘All certainty arises from the comparison of ideas, and from the discovery of such relations as are unalterable, so long as the ideas continue the same.’ 30 Claims like these are true only if the Constitutive Account is. If the Constitutive Account were false, then a knower’s ideas of knowable relations remaining the same would be no guarantee that the relations themselves ‘continue the same’ or not (i.e. hold or not). The Constitutive Account being Hume’s position provides the only explanation of what Peter Millican describes as Hume’s ‘slide between what is implied by the properties of the objects themselves (independently of further information about their relative situation etc.) and what is implied by the ideas of the objects themselves (independently of other ideas).’ 31 Admittedly, the passages I have presented so far do not find Hume asserting that every instance of knowledge must be a perception. Hume uses the term ‘idea’ but not ‘impression’. 12 However, there is nothing about the content of Hume’s position that precludes impressions from being instances of knowledge. Impressions can have the knowable relations as objects in precisely the same way that ideas can, and Hume’s justification of the standards of knowledge is perfectly general in that it does not turn on any of the features distinctive of ideas. Nonetheless, with the preceding argument for attributing the Constitutive Account to Hume in hand, I will provide specific textual evidence for the possibility (and actuality) of Humean sensory knowledge in section 4. This will be the last piece of the puzzle. First, though, I must respond to some objections. 3. ANSWERING OBJECTIONS AND SIZING UP THE COMPETITION 3.1 - What about general knowledge? A natural concern about the Constitutive Account is that it severely restricts what can be known. One might think that an expansion of the domain of the knowable is warranted since, in some cases, it seems that in virtue of knowing whether a token knowable relation holds of one thing, I would also know something about other things of the same sort. This objection can be expressed in terms of what Hume calls ‘adequate representation’. If my idea of a particular right triangle is an adequate representation of all other right triangles, then it seems that whatever I know about this triangle in virtue of it being a right triangle is merely one case of the knowledge that I have about all right triangles whatsoever. In the following passage, Hume defines this sort of adequacy and he explicitly links it to our attainment of knowledge, thereby potentially undermining the attribution of the Constitutive Account to him: Wherever ideas are adequate representations of objects, the relations, contradictions and agreements of the ideas are all applicable to the objects; and this we may in general observe to be the foundation of all human knowledge. (T 1.2.2.1) 15 that adequate representation is ‘the foundation of all human knowledge.’ When the mind is functioning properly, adequate representation magnifies the relevance and usefulness of the knowledge it previously had. 3.2 - A competitor: the Assurance Account Hume gives an explicit definition of knowledge in a passage outside of T 1.3.1 and the subsequent section. Those who reject the attribution of the Constitutive Account to Hume could rely on this passage to justify an alternative interpretation. Unfortunately, T 1.3.1-2 lack a correspondingly explicit definition—in fact, this definition is the only explicit definition of knowledge Hume gives in his entire corpus. In this subsection, I will examine the most plausible version of this sort of alternative interpretation. By addressing this passage and related texts, I will add further credence to my preceding claims about how we should understand Hume’s views on the possibility of general knowledge. The passage containing the explicit definition is as follows. I will call it the Definition Passage. Those philosophers, who have divided human reason into knowledge and probability, and have defin’d the first to be that evidence, which arises from the comparison of ideas, are oblig’d to comprehend all our arguments from causes or effects under the general term of probability. But tho’ every one be free to use his terms in what sense he pleases; and accordingly in the precedent part of this discourse, I have follow’d this method of expression; ‘tis however certain, that in common discourse we readily affirm, that many arguments from causation exceed probability, and may be receiv’d as a superior kind of evidence. One wou’d appear ridiculous, who wou’d say, that ‘tis only probable the sun will rise to-morrow, or that all men must dye; tho’ ‘tis plain we have no farther assurance of these facts, than what experience affords us. For this reason, ‘twou’d perhaps be more 16 convenient, in order at once to preserve the common signification of words, and mark the several degrees of evidence, to distinguish human reason into three kinds, viz. that from knowledge, from proofs, and from probabilities. By knowledge, I mean the assurance arising from the comparison of ideas. By proofs, those arguments, which are deriv’d from the relation of cause and effect, and which are entirely free from doubt and uncertainty. By probability, that evidence, which is still attended with uncertainty. (T 1.3.11.2) In this passage, Hume explicitly asserts that knowledge is ‘the assurance arising from the comparison of ideas’ and he attributes a similar definition (‘that evidence, which arises from the comparison of ideas’) to ‘those philosophers, who have divided human reason into knowledge and probability.’ Given that Hume is one such philosopher and the latter definition is similar to the former, it seems that Hume means to be expressing a similar definition with both, as well as his endorsement of it, or so the defender of the alternative interpretation could argue. Call this interpretation the Assurance Account. 34 But what is the relevant sort of assurance like? In the other Treatise passages where it is clear that Hume is using ‘assurance’ in connection with knowledge, he uses it to refer to dispositions rather than perceptions. 35 From these texts, we can gather that it is a cluster of dispositions to think, to act, and to affirm as if one has the relevant knowable relation(s) immediately present to the mind. Consider the following passage in which Hume discusses the assurance that a geometer has in geometrical propositions and principles: Our ideas seem to give a perfect assurance, that no two right lines can have a common segment; but if we consider these ideas, we shall find, that they always suppose a sensible inclination of the two lines, and that where the angle they form is extremely small, we 17 have no standard of a right line so precise as to assure us of the truth of this proposition. ‘Tis the same case with most of the primary decisions of the mathematics. (T 1.3.1.4) This passage and an earlier passage indicate that Hume maintains that geometers seem to have ‘perfect assurance’—or ‘infallible assurance’ as he describes it in the earlier passage (T 1.2.4.30)—in universal geometrical claims like the view that ‘no two right lines can have a common segment’. Hume does not deny that geometers have assurance in these universal claims. Hume’s concern is with whether this assurance is actually—and not merely seemingly—’perfect’ or ‘infallible’. In this passage, the reason Hume expresses for his concern is the fact that there are cases of two straight (‘right’) lines where the geometer does not have a perception of them lacking a common segment because the geometer’s ideas are not up to the task. Both the eye and the mind’s eye cannot represent the lines in the necessary fashion when the angle between them is not ‘sensible’. Hume argues that once the geometer inspects ‘most of the primary decisions’ of geometry, which come in the form of universal claims like this one, she finds that there is not a precise enough ‘standard’ to justify her assurance in them. Hume’s concern is with epistemic certainty, not psychological certainty. 36 This entails that the geometer’s assurance in the universal claims of her science could not be identical to perceptions of token knowable relations holding (or failing to hold) between their parts, whatever else it is like. If members of this species of assurance were perceptions of token knowable relations holding (or failing to hold) between their parts, then there would be no possibility that she finds herself, upon reconsideration, incapable of evaluating the truth or falsehood of the universal claim when instantiated to cases like the case at hand. Hume is clear that the problem generalizes to all ideas of right lines ‘where the angle they form is extremely small’. As we have seen, perceptions of token knowable relations holding (or failing to hold) 20 possibility of error. After all, at any time when one has assurance but no longer has an idea of the things at issue, one could be mistaken about whether a token knowable relation holds between them or not. One could demonstrate some arithmetical claim, forget the demonstration, and nonetheless have assurance in it. Since Hume is clear in T 1.3.1 that there must no possibility that a knower is in error about what she knows, he must deny that this assurance is knowledge and thus the Assurance Account could not be his position on knowledge. Indeed, this is the very reason that the passage about the geometer’s ‘perfect assurance’ is found in T 1.3.1. Hume is contrasting the geometer’s assurance with knowledge, hence his descriptions of geometry as never attaining ‘a perfect precision and exactness’ and as having first principles ‘drawn from the general appearance of the objects; and that appearance can never afford us any security’. In the very next passage, T 1.3.1.5, Hume concludes that ‘[t]here remain, therefore, algebra and arithmetic as the only sciences, in which we can carry on a chain of reasoning to any degree of intricacy, and yet preserve a perfect exactness and certainty.’ This interpretation of Hume’s position on the species of assurance connected to knowledge is congruent with my response to the challenge of general knowledge. In the preceding subsection, I argued that the sense in which Hume means us to understand his claim that adequate representation is ‘the foundation of all human knowledge’ is as a reference to how we associate relevantly similar ideas of token knowable relations via common terms and thereby know in some derivative sense those token knowable relations that are not immediately present to the mind. My present contention should be understood as the claim that the species of assurance connected to knowledge is a cluster of dispositions that includes such associations. In fact, in the problem cases previously discussed, where the geometer has unjustified assurance, the geometer mistakenly associates ideas with a term (or a sentence composed of terms) that are 21 not similar in the relevant respects. Cases of misclassification like these undergird my claim that these associations should be, at best, understood as fallible effects of our knowledge. The defender of the Constitutive Account can grant that the mind is generally reliable in generating the relevant sort of assurance only from perceptions of the knowable relations of the right sort and in applying this assurance to the good cases. Yet, for Hume, knowledge is a matter of certainty, not mere reliability. In this way, only the Constitutive Account respects Hume’s standards for knowledge. Further credence is lent to this interpretation by the fact that it conforms to how many commentators interpret Locke’s use of the term ‘assurance’ in connection with knowledge. Locke’s influence on Hume in this domain, as elsewhere, was significant. As Samuel C. Rickless and Keith Allen note, Locke does not explicitly use ‘assurance’ to refer to knowledge in the strict sense, although he does use it to refer to habitual knowledge, as well as sensitive knowledge. 41 Of the former, Locke asserts that In his adherence to a Truth, where the Demonstration, by which it was at first known, is forgot, though a Man may be thought rather to believe his Memory, than really know, and this way of entertaining a Truth seem’d formerly to me like something between Opinion and Knowledge, a sort of Assurance which exceeds bare Belief […]. (E IV.i.9) 42 This conforms to how Hume describes the assurance that ‘may continue after the comparison is forgot’ (T 1.3.4.3). As for sensitive knowledge, it is disputed whether it is knowledge in the strict sense by Locke’s lights, but Rickless maintains that it is not because it is assurance, and assurance, for Locke, is ‘a kind of less-than-certain judgment […] founded in the highest possible degree of probability.’ 43 Rickless argues that what ‘leads Locke to give such assurance the name of ‘knowledge’ (even though assurance is not the same as knowledge, strictly 22 understood) is that, for practical purposes, there is little or no difference between assurance and (strict) knowledge.’ 44 This seems to be precisely Hume’s position, as he makes the same point at the end of his discussion of geometry in T 1.3.1.6 when he asserts that generally the shortcuts the mind takes in geometrical reasoning when it lacks ideas of knowable relations ‘cannot lead us into any considerable error.’ 3.3 - Further objections considered Now I will consider three further objections. First, if the Constitutive Account is Hume’s position and Humean knowledge is not the assurance arising from ideas of tokens of the knowable relations, then it seems the Definition Passage must be interpreted as misleading or, worse, as containing a false definition. This is a significant interpretative cost to pay. However, a close inspection of the relevant lines of the Definition Passage reveals another option. Consider, in particular, the latter half of the passage. Hume states that he plans to ‘mark the several degrees of evidence, to distinguish human reason into three kinds, viz. that from knowledge, from proofs, and from probabilities.’ This statement is rather confusing. It seems like there are distinct topics here: the three kinds of reasoning recognized by Hume and then the ‘several degrees of evidence’ that are possessed by their fruits. Note the use of the term ‘from’ before each of the three kinds. Should we take his concern here to be with the evidence that we get from knowledge, from proofs, and from probability, and not with knowledge itself, proof itself, or probability itself? It is unclear. We could interpret the definitions as definitions of the evidence arising from knowledge, proofs, and probability, or we could interpret them as definitions of knowledge, proofs, and probability themselves. I resolve this ambiguity in the following manner. This passage is Hume’s recognition that the conventional linguistic usage of the term ‘knowledge’ is not limited to occurrent knowledge 25 as follows. If Hume were to hold the Constitutive Account, then surely Hume should not assert here that knowable relations could be instantiated by bodies. According to the Constitutive Account, all instances of knowledge are immediately present perceptions, and bodies are not immediately present perceptions. Yet, on any interpretation of Hume where mind-independent things like bodies are immediately present to the mind, he could endorse the Constitutive Account and maintain that we could have knowledge of them. If Hume’s considered position on the metaphysics of immediately present impressions is that of ordinary people (the ‘vulgar’, as he describes them in T 1.4.2), then Hume is a direct realist who allows knowledge of knowable relations holding between mind-independent things. For instance, if a green blade of grass and a green leaf are mind-independent things and yet they are immediately present to the mind, then one can know that they resemble with respect to greenness at the time that they are immediately present. Few commentators interpret Hume as endorsing the direct realist position discussed in T 1.4.2. Hume is widely read as arguing there that we believe that our immediately present perceptions are bodies, but that our beliefs can be shown to be false. 50 Nevertheless, Hume prefaces Book 3 of the Treatise with an ‘Advertisement’ that reveals that he wants the book to be ‘understood by ordinary readers’: I think it proper to inform the public, that tho’ this be a third volume of the Treatise of Human Nature, yet ‘tis in some measure independent of the other two, and requires not that the reader shou’d enter into all the abstract reasonings contain’d in them. I am hopeful it may be understood by ordinary readers, with as little attention as is usually given to any books of reasoning. It must only be observ’d, that I continue to make use of the terms, impressions and ideas, in the same sense as formerly; and that by impressions 26 I mean our stronger perceptions, such as our sensations, affections and sentiments; and by ideas the fainter perceptions, or the copies of these in the memory and imagination. This statement is Hume’s signal that he will not be presuming either of the alternative metaphysical positions on the nature of bodies that he considers in T 1.4.2, especially given their complexity. The first alternative is an indirect realism, where one’s mind-dependent immediately present perceptions can, at best, represent mind-independent things distinct from them. 51 The second alternative is a variety of solipsism, where one’s mind-dependent immediately present perceptions cannot represent anything but other such perceptions. 52 Since Hume argues in T 1.4.2 that ‘ordinary readers’ identify some of their impressions with bodies, this is what Hume is presuming in T 3.1.1—and it is under the presumption of the truth of this identification that one can know that knowable relations hold between bodies. T 3.1.1.19 and similar passages should be understood as referring to this sort of view of the metaphysics of bodies. If Hume himself denies that any mind-independent things could be immediately present perceptions, then he must deny that knowledge could extend beyond one’s mental states or objects. All of the relata of known knowable relations must be immediately present to the mind and, on the two aforementioned alternatives to direct realism, no mind-independent things could be immediately present in this way. Therefore, our knowledge could not extend beyond our mental states or objects on these two alternative metaphysical views. 4. HUMEAN SENSORY KNOWLEDGE In this section, I will argue that Hume holds that there is sensory knowledge. Given that impressions are the perceptions involved in sense perception, this means that, on my interpretation, Hume maintains that some impressions are instances of knowledge because they are at least partially constituted by the tokens of the knowable relations that they have as objects. 27 The texts that I will rely upon to argue for this claim are found in the Treatise and provide further evidence for attributing the Constitutive Account to Hume. The first such passage finds Hume making a distinction between sense perception and reasoning: All kinds of reasoning consist in nothing but a comparison, and a discovery of those relations, either constant or inconstant, which two or more objects bear to each other. This comparison we may make, either when both objects are present to the senses, or when neither of them is present, or when only one. When both the objects are present to the senses along with the relation, we call this perception rather than reasoning; nor is there in this case any exercise of the thought, or any action, properly speaking, but a mere passive admission of the impressions thro’ the organs of sensation. (T 1.3.2.2) Hume uses ‘constant’ and ‘inconstant’ here to refer, respectively, to the knowledge and probability relations. 53 As we have seen, knowable relations hold constant in virtue of the intrinsic properties of their relata, whereas probability relations do not. In the second sentence, Hume makes a threefold distinction that cuts across both kinds of relations. Hume states that when we compare objects and form perceptions of philosophical relations, the relata can be such that both are present to the senses, neither is present to the senses, or only one is present to the senses. When both are present to the senses, along with the relation, Hume claims that ‘we call this perception rather than reasoning’. This claim is made in connection with the opening sentence, wherein Hume claims that ‘all kinds of reasoning consist in nothing but a comparison, and a discovery of those relations, either constant or inconstant, which two or more objects bear to each other.’ Hume’s view, then, is that reasoning is constituted by perceptions of relations where at least one relata is not present to the senses, whereas sense perception of relations is constituted by perceptions of relations where both relata are present to the senses. 30 when their difference is considerable. And this decision we always pronounce at first sight, without any enquiry or reasoning. (T 1.3.1.2) In this passage, Hume begins by distinguishing the three probability relations from the four knowable relations. Next, Hume argues that contrarieties, resemblances, and qualitative relations are ‘discoverable at first sight’. This reference to vision, made several times in the passage, is Hume’s way of emphasizing that the senses enable us to perceive tokens of these three knowable relations. So long as token colors, tastes, feelings, and the like are sufficiently different, Hume asserts that we perceive that they bear one or more of these three knowable relations to each other. Note that Hume states that we perceive token knowable relations holding between impressions ‘without any enquiry or reasoning.’ Given the context, it is clear that the contrast to which Hume refers here is the very same contrast between sense perception and reasoning that he introduces in the passage I quoted previously in this section (T 1.3.2.2). 58 This reading is buttressed by Hume’s comment that these three knowable relations ‘fall more properly under the province of intuition than demonstration.’ Only if vision, smell, touch, and the other sensory modalities provide immediate access in the same way that intuition does would Hume make such an assertion; since Hume implies that the ‘province of intuition’ is broader than vision, smell, or touch alone, his view seems to be that sensing knowable relations is a way of intuiting them. In the subsequent passage (T 1.3.1.3), Hume considers whether proportions in quantity or number—tokens of the fourth kind of knowable relation—can be perceived. Hume argues that generally they cannot, since most of the time we ‘can only guess’ at whether two quantities bear some exact proportion to one another. 59 But Hume grants that there may be some cases involving ‘very short numbers, or very limited portions of extension; which are comprehended in an 31 instant, and where we perceive an impossibility of falling into any considerable error.’ Thus Hume holds that tokens of all four knowable relations can be perceived, although some are more commonly perceived than others. Since there are not any other texts that cut against this interpretation, we are justified in interpreting Hume as arguing that there is sensory knowledge, despite the relative brevity of his statements. 60 These passages are most naturally read under the presumption that the Constitutive Account is Hume's position. Hume’s phrasing indicates that he holds that we know at the same time that we perceive tokens of the knowable relations via sense, and he gives no reason to read him in a contrary fashion. There is no mention of assurance or of any mental processes that must occur before knowledge is acquired in the kinds of cases discussed. This is exactly what we would expect if the Constitutive Account is Hume's position. 5. CONCLUSION In this paper, I have argued that Hume’s justification of his view on the ‘objects of knowledge and certainty’ in T 1.3.1 reveals his standards for knowledge. Since these standards permit both ideas and impressions to qualify as instances of knowledge, Hume’s account of knowledge—the Constitutive Account—makes room for sensory knowledge constituted by impressions. None of the details of Hume’s argumentation in T 1.3.1 preclude intuitive knowledge of this variety, and the textual evidence from T 1.3.1 and the subsequent section further strengthens the case. Given that Hume holds that instances of this sort of knowledge are realized in every case where one’s impressions have token knowable relations between their parts, it is ubiquitous. While Hume is rightly labeled an empiricist for many different reasons, a close inspection of his account of knowledge reveals yet another way in which he merits the label. 61 32 1 I will use T, A, and EHU to cite Hume’s Treatise, its Abstract, and his first Enquiry, respectively. Quotations are from the Clarendon edition of the works of David Hume: Thomas L. Beauchamp (ed.), An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2001); and David Fate Norton and Mary J. Norton (eds.), A Treatise of Human Nature, two volumes (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2007), the latter of which includes the Abstract. My references are to Clarendon paragraph numbers. 2 In the first Enquiry, for instance, Hume uses ‘knowledge’ in many different colloquial senses, and the few passages related to knowledge as Hume describes it in T 1.3.1 must be understood through the fuller picture given by the Treatise. See, e.g., EHU 1.8, EHU 4.4, or EHU 5.22. For discussion and a similar reading to mine, see Frederick F. Schmitt, Hume’s Epistemology in the Treatise: A Veritistic Interpretation [Hume’s Epistemology in the Treatise] (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014), 41. 3 Although Hume never explicitly analyzes the nature of propositions, it seems that he maintains that propositions are the perceptions that linguistic that-clauses express. See T 1.1.1.7, T 1.1.7.3, T 1.1.7.8, T 1.1.7.14, T 1.2.6.2-3, T 1.3.3.2-3, T 1.3.6.4, T 1.3.7.3, T 3.1.1.27, A 7, A 18, and A 21. The subject-predicate structure of that-clauses indicates that the relevant perceptions are generally complex, and philosophical relations are the best candidates in Hume’s system (the alternatives are modes and substances; see T 1.1.4.7). Numerical identity and existential statements are potential exceptions (see T 1.4.2.26 and T 1.3.7.5n20, respectively). For discussion, see David Owen, Hume’s Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 74n109, 103-104. 35 12 For relevant cases where Hume uses ‘infallible’ and its cognates, see, e.g., T 1.3.1.5, T 1.3.3.2, and T 1.4.1.1. For relevant cases where Hume uses ‘certain’ and its cognates, see, e.g., T 1.3.1.2, T 1.3.1.6, T 1.3.3.2, T 1.3.3.3, T 1.3.6.7, and T 1.3.12.14. 13 See, e.g., T 1.3.2.1 and T 1.3.3.9. For discussion of scientia, certainty, and Hume’s antecedents, see Owen, Hume’s Reason, 17-23, 36-38, 83-84. See also Nicholas Jolley, ‘Scientia and Self-knowledge in Descartes’ in Tom Sorell, G.A. Rogers, and Jill Kraye (eds.), Scientia in Early Modern Philosophy: Seventeeth-Century Thinkers on Demonstrative Knowledge from First Principles (Heidelberg: Springer, 2010), 83-97; Tom Sorell, ‘Scientia and Science in Descartes’ in Tom Sorell, G.A. Rogers, and Jill Kraye (eds.), Scientia in Early Modern Philosophy: Seventeeth-Century Thinkers on Demonstrative Knowledge from First Principles (Heidelberg: Springer, 2010), 71-82; Schmitt, Hume’s Epistemology in the Treatise, 50-81; and De Pierris, Ideas, Evidence, and Method, 97-98. 14 Schmitt, Hume’s Epistemology in the Treatise, 71. See the subsequent pages for further discussion. Note that I disagree with Schmitt’s position that infallibility, for Hume, is ultimately to be understood in terms of necessary reliability. See note 34. 15 Note that Hume’s justification indicates that there may be some resemblances, proportions in quantity or number, qualitative relations, and contrarieties that are objects of probability. For instance, the relative heaviness of two objects mentioned by Hume in T 1.1.5.5 is a relation ‘of which we receive information from experience’ and which is ‘never discoverable merely from their ideas’ (T 1.3.1.1). Likewise, although we know that 3-1=2, we do not know that this proportion in quantity or number is instantiated by any beings which are not perceptions or their parts (more on this issue later in this section). And while some relations in space and time, identities (over time), and causal relations are objects of probability, some are objects of 36 knowledge. There are two-dimensional spatial relations that hold between the colored points that are immediately visible to me right now that ‘depend entirely on the ideas, which we compare together’ (T 1.3.1.1) and that are ‘discoverable at first sight, and fall more properly under the province of intuition than demonstration’ (T 1.3.1.2). Nothing extrinsic to my complex idea of the visual array before me needs to cooperate for me to know that a patch of red is between two patches of blue. In T 1.3.1, Hume seems to be too cavalier about how clean this distinction between the two classes of relations really is. 16 For discussion, see Miren Boehm, ‘Certainty, Necessity, and Knowledge in Hume’s Treatise’ in Stanley Tweyman (ed.), David Hume: A Tercentenary Tribute (Ann Arbor, MI: Caravan Books, 2013), 67-84, at 68, 76-79. 17 See also T 1.1.7.6 and A 11. 18 See, e.g., T 1.3.6.1, T 1.3.9.10, and T 1.3.14.13. 19 This is the link to Hume’s negative views on the ‘necessary connexion’ between causes and their effects. See T 1.3.14.15-23. 20 For extensive discussion of this feature of perceptions and related issues, see Hsueh Qu, ‘Hume on Mental Transparency’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 98 (2017), 576-601. Hsueh Qu argues that Hume holds that ‘[w]e cannot fail to apprehend the qualitative characters of our current perceptions, and these apprehensions cannot fail to be veridical’ (Qu, ‘Hume on Mental Transparency’, 577). Since Qu holds that ‘the intrinsic qualities of a perception seem limited to its qualitative character’ (Qu, ‘Hume on Mental Transparency’, 582), it follows that this view, which Qu calls ‘Qualitative Transparency’, applies to intrinsic properties. For discussion, see J.A. Passmore, Hume’s Intentions (London: Duckworth, 1980), 90; and Jonathan Cottrell, ‘Minds, Composition, and Hume’s Skepticism in the Appendix’, 544. 37 21 Although the dialectic in T 1.4.2 is complex, the view expressed in T 1.4.2.47 is expressed in Hume’s own voice. In the paragraph prior, Hume abandons the temporary identification of ‘perception’ with ‘object’ that he had sustained from T 1.4.2.31. Hume says he will once again ‘distinguish […] betwixt perceptions and objects’ in the way that the ‘modern philosophers’ (like Locke) do. Hume then proceeds to argue in his own voice in T 1.4.2.47 that the hypothesis ‘that our objects alone preserve a continu’d existence’ while our immediately present perceptions do not has ‘no primary recommendation’ with regard to reason. It is in this argument that Hume relies on the claim that I attribute to him that ‘the only existences, of which we are certain, are perceptions, which [are] immediately present to us by consciousness’. 22 See T 1.3.2.3, T 1.4.2.5, T 1.4.7.3, and T 2.2.6.2. In the first Enquiry, Hume seems to have a similar view. See EHU 7.11 and EHU 7.13. 23 For cases where Hume describes perceptions as ‘appearances’ (or uses ‘appear’ or its cognates with respect to them), see, e.g., T 1.1.1.1, T 1.1.3.1, T 1.1.4.2, T 1.2.1.5, T 1.2.2.1, T 1.2.3.4, T 1.2.3.10, and T 1.2.6.8. See especially T 1.1.7.3-4 and T 1.2.5.26n12.2App. 24 Of course, as Samuel C. Rickless discusses (‘Hume’s distinction between impressions and ideas’, European Journal of Philosophy, 26 [2018], 1222-1237), there are other interpretations of the impression-idea distinction. However, there is only one interpretation of the distinction under which Hume holds that the misattributed property (of being an idea) is an intrinsic one. This is the interpretation under which Hume’s view is that the distinction between impressions and ideas ‘consists in the degrees of force and liveliness with which they strike upon the mind’ (T 1.1.1.1), where ‘force and liveliness’ is interpreted as referring to phenomenal intensity. While I agree that ‘force and liveliness’ should be interpreted in this way, the other aspect of the interpretation is implausible for the reasons Rickless cites, and all of the other interpretations of Hume’s 40 that the relations hold on the objects, given the existence of the objects as represented by the ideas. We do not know that these relations hold on the objects unconditionally.’ 32 For the most straightforward case where Locke contests this view, see E III.iii.7-9. 33 For a congenial summary of Hume’s position on abstract ideas, see Garrett, Hume, 52-60. For a competing picture and an account of the interpretative geography, see Landy, ‘A Puzzle about Hume’s Theory of General Representation’. 34 I give it this name because, aside from the Definition Passage, Hume uses ‘assurance’ rather than ‘evidence’ to refer to what ‘arises from the comparison of ideas’. The Assurance Account is the most common interpretation of Hume’s position on knowledge defended in the secondary literature, but its defenders do not defend it at great length. Proponents include Kingsley Blake Price (‘Does Hume’s Theory of Knowledge Determine his Ethical Theory’, 427); Don Garrett (Cognition and Commitment, 170); Kevin Meeker (‘Hume on Knowledge, Certainty, and Probability: Anticipating the Disintegration of the Analytic/Synthetic Divide?’, 229); and Louis E. Loeb (Stability and Justification in Hume’s Treatise [Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002], 61fn1, and ‘Inductive Inference in Hume’s Philosophy’ in Elizabeth Radcliffe (ed.), A Companion to Hume [Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell, 2008], 106-125, at 106). Many apparently relevant discussions of Hume’s position on knowledge, like that in Harold W. Noonan, Hume on Knowledge (London: Routledge, 1999), in fact concern Hume’s relationship with contemporary positions on knowledge. An exception is that of Schmitt (Hume’s Epistemology in the Treatise, ch. 2). Schmitt attributes to Hume the view that knowledge is cognition that is ‘necessarily reliable’. Full engagement with Schmitt’s interpretation would take me too far afield, but I will make three brief remarks. First, I deny, contra Schmitt (Hume’s Epistemology in the Treatise, 73- 75), that Hume holds that one’s consciousness of one’s immediately present perceptions provides 41 knowledge of their existence, given that this is not a knowable relation. Second, I deny, contra Schmitt (Hume’s Epistemology in the Treatise, 69-72), that the primary sense of ‘infallible’ that Hume applies to knowledge refers to a feature of the operations that produce it. Knowledge is infallible in Hume’s primary sense because the knower cannot err with respect to the known, regardless of the operations by which it comes about. In the case of intuition, it is especially clear that the features of the operations of the faculties that it arises from are entirely irrelevant. Third, Schmitt’s interpretation is incomplete because it does not specify the relationship between instances of knowledge and their objects. Although Schmitt’s account is a viable alternative, and there are many aspects of his analyses that I agree with, I maintain that the Assurance Account is the most plausible alternative to the Constitutive Account since it is supported by the Definition Passage, which contains Hume’s only explicit definition of knowledge and seems to straightforwardly undermine it. Furthermore, it is the Humean version of one of the accounts of knowledge attributed to Locke in the secondary literature. This latter connection significantly increases its prima facie plausibility, given the links and affinities between the two thinkers on these issues. See the end of this subsection for discussion. 35 See T 1.2.4.25, T 1.2.4.30, T 1.3.1.4, T 1.3.4.3, T 1.3.13.19, T 1.4.2.14, and T 2.3.10.2. 36 This parallels Locke’s treatment of certainty. For discussion, see Schmitt, Hume’s Epistemology in the Treatise, 58-62. 37 For discussion, see Emil Badici, ‘Standards of Equality and Hume’s View of Geometry’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 92 (2011), 448-467; and Graciela De Pierris, ‘Hume on space, geometry, and diagrammatic reasoning’, Synthese, 186 (2012), 169-189. 42 38 In T 1.3.13.19, Hume corroborates this reading in a discussion of the relationship between assurance and memory. Hume argues that our confidence in the faculty of memory rivals the assurance derived from demonstrations, thereby revealing that he sees the notions as similar. 39 See T 1.3.3.1-3 for an argument of Hume’s that assumes this dualistic view. 40 For a concise description of how demonstrations are structured, see Owen, Hume’s Reason, 98-99. 41 See Samuel C. Rickless, ‘Is Locke’s Theory of Knowledge Inconsistent?’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 77:1 (2008), 83-104, at 85, 93, 93n10; and Keith Allen, ‘Locke and Sensitive Knowledge’, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 51:2 (2013), 249-266, at 251-252. On habitual knowledge, see E II.xxxii.6, and E IV.i.8-9. On sensitive knowledge, see E IV.xi.2- 8. See also E I.i.2, E I.iii.13, E IV.xv.2, E IV.xvi.6, and E IV.xvi.14. For further discussion, see also Jennifer Nagel, ‘Sensitive Knowledge: Locke on Skepticism and Sensation’ in Matthew Stuart (ed.), A Companion to Locke (Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell, 2016), 313-333, at 318. See the next note for primary text citation information for Locke. 42 As some of his qualifications here indicate, Locke ultimately argues, of this variety of habitual knowledge, that ‘upon a due examination I find it comes not short of perfect certainty, and is in effect true Knowledge.’ It is until he makes this decision that he labels it ‘assurance’. As for this abbreviation, I am using E to cite Locke’s Essay. Quotations are from the Clarendon edition of the works of John Locke: P.H. Nidditch (ed.), An Essay concerning Human Understanding (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975). My references are to Clarendon paragraph numbers. 43 Rickless, ‘Is Locke’s Theory of Knowledge Inconsistent?’, 85. See also Samuel C. Rickless, ‘Locke’s “Sensitive Knowledge”: Knowledge or Assurance?’ in Daniel Garber and Donald 45 Radical Empiricism’, Hume Studies, 37:2 (2011), 189-210); and Kenneth Winkler (‘Hume on Scepticism and the Senses’ in Donald C. Ainslie & Annemarie Butler [eds.], The Cambridge Companion to Hume’s Treatise [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015], 135-164). 53 For discussion, see Millican, ‘Hume’s Fork’, 17-18. 54 Note that this means that I hold that sensory impressions represent, even in isolation. They represent parts of themselves—namely, what Donald C. Ainslie calls their ‘image-content’ (‘Adequate Ideas and Modest Scepticism in Hume’s Metaphysics of Space’, Archiv fur Geschichte de Philosophie, 92 [2010], 39-67, at 47). For a competing picture, see Schmitt, Hume’s Epistemology in the Treatise, 67-69. 55 As Owen (Hume’s Reason, 9) puts it, ‘Two ideas are demonstratively related if the relation between them is conceived, not immediately, but via other intermediate ideas. The link between each pair of adjacent ideas in the resulting chain must be intuitive.’ For discussion, see Owen, Hume’s Reason, 93-98. 56 As Garrett puts it, intuition is an ‘immediate apprehension of relations of ideas’ and ‘immediate and non-inferential’. For the former, see Don Garrett, ‘“A Small Tincture of Pyrrhonism”: Skepticism and Naturalism in Hume’s Science of Man’ in Walter Sinnott- Armstrong (ed.), Pyrrhonian Skepticism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), 68-98, at 98n39. For the latter, see Garrett, Hume, 90. 57 For further discussion of this connection with Locke, see De Pierris, Ideas, Evidence, and Method, 51-62. 58 See also T 1.3.6.6. 59 See also T 1.2.4.23. 46 60 Commentators who agree that Hume holds that some tokens of the knowable relations are perceived in visual experience include Kingsley Blake Price (‘Does Hume’s Theory of Knowledge Determine his Ethical Theory?’, 427-428); Garrett (Hume, 92); Millican (‘Hume’s Fork’, 46-48); Miren Boehm (‘Certainty, Necessity, and Knowledge in Hume’s Treatise’, 73- 74); and Inukai (‘Hume on Relations: Are They Real?’, 195-202). Norton (David Hume: Common-Sense Moralist, Sceptical Metaphysician [Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1982], 228n77) argues that it is not Hume’s ‘official position’, which may be compatible with my interpretation. There are others who argue that some tokens of the knowable relations are perceivable and yet contingent because their relata are themselves matters of fact. See Owen, Hume’s Reason, 95; Owen, ‘Hume and the Mechanics of Mind: Impressions, Ideas, and Association’, 83; and Helen Beebee, Hume on Causation (London: Routledge, 2006), 21, 24. Yet, every commentator—with the possible exception of Millican, who seems to argue in passing that Hume should hold that there is intuitive sensory knowledge—denies that (or is silent on the question of whether) any impression could itself be knowledge. See, e.g., Boehm, ‘Certainty, Necessity, and Knowledge in Hume’s Treatise’, 73-75, 79-81. 61 First and foremost, I would like to thank Samuel Newlands and Don Garrett. They patiently reviewed seemingly innumerable versions of this paper and they have helped me minimize the errors it contains, though I am sure many remain. I would also like to thank Blake Roeber, Katharina Kraus, and Lizzie Fricker, as well as several anonymous reviewers and Donald Rutherford at OSEMP, for their invaluable feedback and helpful comments on prior versions of this paper. Finally, I would like to thank the participants at my talk ‘Hume and Perceptual Knowledge’ at the University of Notre Dame on December 7, 2018 for their constructive comments and questions.
Docsity logo



Copyright © 2024 Ladybird Srl - Via Leonardo da Vinci 16, 10126, Torino, Italy - VAT 10816460017 - All rights reserved