Docsity
Docsity

Prepare for your exams
Prepare for your exams

Study with the several resources on Docsity


Earn points to download
Earn points to download

Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan


Guidelines and tips
Guidelines and tips

Nelson Goodness: Ways of Worldmaking - Metaphysics | PHIL 420, Study notes of Philosophy

Material Type: Notes; Class: Metaphysics; Subject: Philosophy; University: California State University - Fullerton; Term: Spring 2008;

Typology: Study notes

Pre 2010

Uploaded on 08/18/2009

koofers-user-kbt
koofers-user-kbt 🇺🇸

10 documents

1 / 7

Toggle sidebar

Related documents


Partial preview of the text

Download Nelson Goodness: Ways of Worldmaking - Metaphysics | PHIL 420 and more Study notes Philosophy in PDF only on Docsity! Goodman 1 Phil 420: Metaphysics Spring 2008 [Handout 10] Professor JeeLoo Liu Nelson Goodman: Ways of Worldmaking [II] § A Puzzle about Perception [Chapter V] The visual system is persistent, inventive, and sometimes rather perverse in building a world according to its own lights; the supplementation is deft, flexible, and often elaborate. [JL: Our eyes/consciousness could “fill in” things that are not there; they can also delete things that are there] Example: ___ We strive mightily and resourcefully, consciously and automatically, to supply whatever is required to join separate pieces into one object or pseudo-object, as in the familiar cases of this figure: But unless we somehow manage – perceptually or conceptually or conjecturally – to fill in between the two separated entities or events, we resist combining them into one thing. * the color phi phenomenon: the illusion of motion Goodman’s interpretation: Virtually every clear case of visual motion perception depends on abrupt shift in color. Goodman 2 The Implications: ___ The task of finding the facts does not become arbitrary or pointless when the facts are of ‘apparent’ rather than of ‘real’ or of physical motion. “Apparent” and “real” here are insidiously prejudicial labels for facts of different kinds. Just as the motion of a dot across a screen is sometimes ‘not there’ in stimulus or object, so the separate static flashes are sometimes ‘not there’ in perception. What we have been looking at are some striking examples of how perception makes its facts. § The Fabrication of Facts [Chapter VI] * Goodman’s declaration: ___ My title, “The fabrication of facts”, has the virtue of … irritating those fundamentalists who know very well that facts are found not made, that facts constitute the one and only real world, and that knowledge consists of believing the facts. These articles of faith so firmly possess most of us, they so bind and blind us, that “fabrication of fact” has a paradoxical sound. “Fabrication” has become a synonym for ‘falsehood” or “fiction” as contrasted with “truth” or “fact.” Of course, we must distinguish falsehood and fiction from truth and fact; but we cannot, I am sure, do it on the ground that fiction is fabricated and fact found. * The perceptual is no more a rather distorted version of the physical facts than the physical is a highly artificial version of the perceptual facts. (92-3) * “Facts” like “meaning” is a syncategorematic (syn·cat·e·gor·e·mat·ic adj used to describe an expression that has meaning only in conjunction with another expression) term; for facts, after all, are obvious factitious (not real or natural but artificial or invented)…. As meanings vanish in favor of certain relationships among terms, so facts vanish in favor of certain relationships among versions. (93) * Facts are theory-laden; they are as theory-laden as we hope our theories are fact-laden. (96-7) * Goodman’s radical relativism (with the following restraints): 1. Willingness to accept countless alternative truth or right world-versions does not mean that everything goes, that tall stories are as good as short ones, that truths are no longer distinguished from falsehoods. 2. However, truth should not be conceived as correspondence with a ready- made world (because there is no “ready-made world”). 3. Though we make worlds by making versions, we do not make a world by putting symbols together at random. 4. Multiple worlds are just the actual worlds made by and answering to true or right versions. 5. False versions (e.g. mere possible worlds) have no place in my philosophy. Goodman 5 While most of use also learned a little later to mistrust [these] fundamental principles, I am afraid that my remark about conflicting truths and multiple actual worlds may be passed over as purely rhetorical. They are not. * The Fabrication of Facts Example: (P) Under the correct system in question, every point has correlated with it a combination of a vertical and a horizontal line. (Q) Under (another) correct system in question, no point has correlated with it a combination of any other elements. These are completely compatible with each other. In any case, if the composition of points of lines or of lines out of points is conventional rather than factual, points and lines themselves are no less so. And so we may regard the disagreements as not about the facts but as due to differences in conventions – of lines, points, regions, and modes of combinations – adopted in organizing or describing the space. * When we strip off as layers of convention all differences among ways of describing it, what is left? The onion is peeled down to its empty core. (118) In short, if we abstract from all features responsible for disagreements between truths we have nothing left but versions without things or facts or worlds. The realist will resist the conclusion that there is no world; the idealist will resist the conclusion that all conflicting versions describe different worlds. As for me, I find these views equally delightful and equally deplorable – for after all, the difference between them is purely conventional. In practice, of course, we draw the line wherever we like, and change it as often as suits our purposes. * Tests and Truth [Or: What constitutes truth?] ___ Possible candidates: correspondence, coherence, utility (pragmatic) Goodman 6 * Even where there is no conflict, truth is far from sufficient. Some truths are trivial, irrelevant, unintelligible, or redundant; too broad, too narrow, too boring, too bizarre, too complicated; etc. * Truth is no more a necessary than a sufficient consideration for a choice of a statement. Not only may the choice often be of a statement that is the more nearly right in other respects over one that is the more nearly true, but where truth is too finicky, too uneven, or does not fit comfortably with other principles, we may choose the nearest amenable and illuminating lie. (121) * We must use some tests in judging truths; and such features as utility and coherence are prominent candidates. That we can readily produce ostensible examples of useless tangled truths and of useful neat falsehoods shows at most only that the tests are corroborative rather than conclusive. (122) * A statement is true, and a description or representation right, for a world it fits. * Rather than attempting to subsume descriptive and representational rightness under truth, we shall subsume truth along with these under the general notion of rightness of fit. (132) § What Constitutes “Rightness”? * A deductive argument is right in a fuller sense only if the premiseses are true and the inferences valid. * An inductive rightness, on the other hand, consists of conformity with principles that codify practice. Inductive validity is one step further removed from truth than is deductive validity, for valid inductive inference from true premises need not yield a true conclusion. (126) Rightness of induction requires: (i) Rightness of predicates projected – we must use only “projectible” predicates (such as ‘green’ and ‘blue’) but not unprojectible ones (such as ‘grue’ or ‘bleen’). (ii) Rightness of inference – The argument must proceed from premiseses consisting of all such true reports on examined instances as are in terms of projectible predicates. (iii) Rightness of categorization – the categories must be inductively right. However, what counts as a “right” category may be due to habits, our inertia, or convenience. Categories that are inductively right tend to coincide with categories that are right for science in general; but variations in purpose may result in variations in relevant kinds. Goodman 7 A primary factor in projectibility is habit, the decision normally goes to the one with the better entrenched predicates. Obviously there must be leeway for progress, for the introduction of novel organizations that make, or take account of, newly important connections and distinctions. Inertia is modified by inquiry and invention, somewhat restrained in turn by entrenched general ‘background’ principles, and so on. Good practice depends upon habit in continual revision under frustration and invention. When the outcomes of rightly made predictions are wrong, the failures may be blamed on bad luck or, if they prominent or plentiful, may call for amendment of what constitutes good practice. (p. 136) According to present practice, the blue-green categorization is right and the grue-bleen categorization wrong as marking the lines along which we make our inductive reasoning. Induction according to nonprojectible categories is not merely awkward but wrong, whatever may be the outcome of the inductive conclusion drawn. § Goodman’s Conclusion: (138-40) 1. Truth of statements and rightness of descriptions, representations, etc., is primarily a matter of fit: fit to what is referred to in one way or another, or to other renderings, or to modes and manners of organization. 2. Knowing or understanding is seen as ranging beyond the acquiring of true beliefs to the discovering and devising of fit of all sorts. 3. Rather than being able to justify our confidence in inductive inference or in the procedures for taking fair samples, we look to the confidence itself for whatever justification there may be for those procedures. 4. The line between artistic and scientific judgment does not coincide with the line between subjective and objective.
Docsity logo



Copyright © 2024 Ladybird Srl - Via Leonardo da Vinci 16, 10126, Torino, Italy - VAT 10816460017 - All rights reserved