Docsity
Docsity

Prepare for your exams
Prepare for your exams

Study with the several resources on Docsity


Earn points to download
Earn points to download

Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan


Guidelines and tips
Guidelines and tips

Understanding the Neuroscientific Perspective on the Concept of Self, Lecture notes of Psychology

The debate surrounding the necessity of the concept of self in psychology, with notable figures such as Allport, Skinner, and Ramachandran raising questions about its role. However, recent renewed interest in the naturalist view of the self, spearheaded by neuroscientists, has led to a better understanding of how the brain builds a sense of self. Topics covered include the neural mechanisms underlying consciousness, affective experience, memory, and self-regulation. Researchers have also discussed the evolutionary origins and genetics of self-esteem and other self processes.

Typology: Lecture notes

2021/2022

Uploaded on 07/05/2022

carol_78
carol_78 🇦🇺

4.8

(53)

1K documents

1 / 64

Toggle sidebar

Related documents


Partial preview of the text

Download Understanding the Neuroscientific Perspective on the Concept of Self and more Lecture notes Psychology in PDF only on Docsity! 1 To appear in: O. P. John, R. W. Robins, & L. A. Pervin (Eds.). Handbook of personality: Theory and research (3rd edition). New York: Guilford. Naturalizing the Self Richard W. Robins University of California, Davis Jessica L. Tracy Kali H. Trzesniewski University of British Columbia University of Western Ontario Draft Date: 8/28/08 Author Note: Correspondence should be addressed to Richard W. Robins, Department of Psychology, University of California, Davis, CA 95616-8686. E-mail may be sent to: rwrobins@ucdavis.edu. 2 Late in his life, Michelangelo began carving what many art historians consider his most mature and provocative sculpture, the Florentine Pieta, an enormous 8 ft. statue he intended to place at the top of his own tomb. After working intensely for a decade on this monumental project, the artist entered his studio one day and, in a fit of rage, assaulted the sculpture with a sledgehammer. He broke off the hands and legs and nearly shattered the work before his assistants dragged him away. Why would Michelangelo attempt to destroy one of his greatest creations, a sculpture that has been described as among the finest works of the Renaissance? How would a personality psychologist answer this question? A trait researcher might say that Michelangelo was highly impulsive and dispositionally prone to negative emotionality. A biologically oriented researcher might speculate that he had a deficiency in the monoamine oxidase A gene, low levels of serotonin, and an atypical pattern of activation in the frontal and temporal lobes. A motivational researcher might assume that Michelangelo’s personal projects shifted and the Florentine Pieta came into conflict with other important goals. Yet none of these explanations provides a completely satisfactory account of Michelangelo’s seemingly irrational act. In our view, it is only through a consideration of self-processes—identity, self-esteem, and self-regulation—that one can begin to understand Michelangelo’s behavior. An analysis of Michelangelo’s “self” allows us to formulate hypotheses concerning a heightened sense of perfectionism and shame that likely accompanied his reputed narcissistic tendencies, a failure to live up to his own expectations and those of his father (who equated sculpting with manual labor), a breakdown in self-regulation, and an identity crisis due to his impending death. Many aspects of human behavior are inexplicable without the notion that people have a self. In fact, an understanding of the self is necessary for a complete understanding of personality processes—the processes that generate and regulate thoughts, feelings, and 5 Koch (2004), Edelman (2005), and others, who study the neural mechanisms underlying consciousness in an attempt to understand how a sense of self emerges from the activity of the brain. Similarly, in their search for the neural bases of affective experience, emotion researchers such as Damasio (2003) and LeDoux (2003)have discovered basic facts about how the brain is wired, which have profound implications for self researchers. Memory researchers have linked various forms of memory to the conscious experience of self (e.g., Tulving, 2005), and this work has been used to examine neural activation during processing of self-relevant information in normal populations (Kelley et al., 2002; Magno & Allan, 2007) and amnesiacs (Klein, Loftus, & Kihlstrom, 1996). Baron-Cohen (2008) and other neurologists (e.g., Feinberg & Paul, 2005) provide vivid illustrations of how neurological disorders such as autism can produce profound deficits in self and identity. Thus, researchers from a wide range of perspectives outside of the traditional boundaries of personality and social psychology are grappling with basic issues about the self. Moreover, within personality and social psychology, there has been an explosion of recent research linking brain mechanisms to self-related processes. Indeed, many of the topics mentioned above as integrating the study of self and personality, have now been studied from a neuroscience perspective, including the neural bases of pride (Takahashi et al., 2007), attachment (Gillath, Bunge, Shaver, Wendelken, & Mikulincer, 2005), autobiographical memory (Levine, 2004), and self-regulation (Inzlicht & Gutsell, 2007). Building on this emerging biological account, researchers have also discussed the evolutionary origins of the self (Sedikides & Skowronski, 2003) and explored the genetics of self-esteem and other self processes (e.g., Neiss et al., 2005; Neiss, Sedikides, & Stevenson, 2006). 6 What unites many of these perspectives is a naturalist view of the self—a belief that the self can be studied like any other natural phenomenon. One goal of this chapter is to help self research recover its roots by reconnecting it with broader scientific concerns. We return to a set of foundational issues that preoccupied William James when he formulated his naturalist perspective of the mind. Overview of Chapter The literature on the self is enormous. In a recent survey of personality psychologists (Robins, Tracy, & Sherman, 2007), 43% of respondents indicated that they study the self- concept and 35% study self-esteem. A Psycinfo search for the keyword “self” identified 265,161 articles.1 Even restricting the search to the past 30 years and to a single journal—the Journal of Personality and Social Psychology—yielded 2,411 articles with the keyword “self” (33% of all articles published in the journal from 1970 to 2007). As Figure 1 shows, research on the self surged in the 1970s—probably reflecting the rise of cognitive psychology and its emphasis on mental events—and then maintained a high level up to the present. In this chapter, we do not attempt to provide a comprehensive review of the voluminous social-personality literature on the self. Several recent books and chapters provide such reviews: see Chen and Pickett (in press), Leary (2004), and Sedikides and Spence (2007) for general overviews of the self literature; Harter (2006) and Robins and Trzesniewski (2005) for research on the development of the self; Tracy, Robins, and Tangney (2007) for research on self and emotions; Gailliot et al. (this volume) for research on self-regulation; Swann (this volume) for research on the role of the self in social interaction; and Byrne (1996) for an overview of self- concept measures. Instead, our goal is to step back and reflect on some broader questions about the self: What is the self? When does the self first emerge and how does it change over time? Is 7 the self distinctive to humans? How does the brain build a sense of self? Is the self a product of evolution? What are the adaptive functions of the self? These questions return us to James’ initial set of concerns when he formulated his naturalist perspective on self and consciousness. Basic Questions about the Self What is the Self? Definitional and Conceptual Issues The question—what is the self?—has been an abiding concern of philosophers, writers, scientists, and laypeople. Although self theorists have offered numerous definitions, there is no consensual framework for conceptualizing the various aspects of the self. Some researchers embrace the theoretical richness of the field, whereas others bemoan its conceptual muddiness. One source of confusion is that the self does not refer to a single entity but rather to myriad structures and processes (Leary, 2004). Consider the example of happiness. One aspect of the self is the feeling or experience of happiness itself. This is what philosophers refer to as qualia or sentience. A second aspect is the conscious recognition that my feeling of happiness belongs to me—it is I who feels happy. As Flanagan (1991) observed, “thoughts, feelings, and the like do not sit around disembodied. All thoughts and feelings are ‘owned,’ that is, all thoughts and feelings occur to someone.” (p. 31). A third aspect refers to attentional focus—I can be aware (i.e., conscious) or not aware of my current state of happiness. For example, I could be feeling happy but not pay attention to this because I am focused on skiing down the mountain. Finally, I can have a stable representation of myself as happy—that is, I can think of myself as a generally happy person, or have the belief that “I always feel happy when I am skiing.” These four examples are only a sampling of the many ways the self has been defined in the literature. Self-awareness and self-representations. In our view, however, all of the definitions boil down to two basic classes of phenomena: (1) an ongoing sense of self-awareness and (2) stable 10 “social self” perspective, people have multiple selves reflecting their various group memberships and associated identities. Consistent with this view, when answering the question "Who am I?", people come up with a vast array of responses that encompass everything from beliefs about private thoughts and feelings, to one’s place in the larger nexus of relationships, social roles, and cultural institutions (Gordon, 1968). Within psychology, the idea that we have multiple selves dates back to James’s (1890) The Principles of Psychology, which included a summary table classifying the levels and structures of the self (p. 329). Figure 3 shows our revised and expanded version of this table (see also Brewer & Gardner, 1996; Brown, 1998; Greenwald & Breckler, 1985). The first row shows the personal or individual self, which reflects people’s beliefs about their private self, including their traits, values, and abilities. The second row shows the relational self, which reflects how people see themselves in intimate relationships. The third row shows the social self, which reflects how people see themselves in more general interpersonal contexts, including their social roles and reputation. The fourth row shows the collective self, which reflects people’s identities concerning their various reference groups, such as their religion, ethnicity, and nationality. Some aspects of identity, such as gender, permeate all levels of the self from the personal (e.g., perceptions of feminine characteristics) to the collective (e.g., one’s identity as a “feminist”). Interestingly, research suggests that information about the personal self (e.g., “altruistic”) may be represented in memory separately (and thus encoded and retrieved separately) from information about the social and collective self (e.g., “peace activist”; Trafimow, Triandis, & Goto, 1991). People derive self-regard differently depending on which level of the self they are representing. For example, when an individual is focused on the personal self, self-esteem is rooted in meeting personal aspiration. However, when an individual is focused on the collective 11 self, self-esteem is rooted in the accomplishments and prestige of the social groups to which the person belongs (Rubin & Hewstone, 1998). A great deal of recent research has demonstrated cross-cultural differences in the degree of emphasis on these various levels of the self. Specifically, Western cultures (e.g., United States) tend to be more focused on the personal self, whereas Eastern cultures (e.g., China, Japan) tend to be more focused on the collective self (e.g., Triandis, 1997). These differences appear to be socialized early in life and persist throughout the lifespan (e.g., Wang, 2006). However, it is important not to overemphasize these cultural differences, given the substantial individual differences that exist within groups. For example, even within Western cultures, women have more collectivistic, interdependent selves, whereas men tend to have more personal, independent selves (Josephs, Markus, & Tafarodi, 1992). Moreover, reviews of the literature on individualism-collectivism have failed to show consistent cultural differences and, in some contexts, individuals from Western cultures do not appear to be any more individualistic or less collectivistic than individuals from Asian cultures (del Prado et al., 2007; Oyserman, Coon, & Kemmelmeier, 2002, but see Schimmack, Oishi, & Diener, 2005). For example, Japanese tend to focus on the personal self (e.g., describe themselves using personality traits) to the same extent as Americans when they are asked to provide self-descriptions in specific contexts such as at home (Kanagawa, Cross, & Markus, 2001). Findings such as these have led to calls for refining the collectivistic construct, including the need to distinguish between relational and group aspects of the collective self (Brewer & Chen, 2007). Nonetheless, the individualism-collectivism distinction does predict differences in self- views. Individuals from East Asian cultures tend to accept and value negative information about the self more than individuals from Western cultures (Oyserman et al., 2002; Spencer-Rodgers, 12 Peng, Wang, & Hou, 2004). Similarly, individuals from East Asian cultures tend to have lower self-esteem than those from most other cultures (Schmitt & Allik, 2005). Interestingly, this difference is only observed for explicit (i.e., self-report) measures of self-esteem, not implicit measures such as the implicit association test or preferences for the initials in one’s own name (Heine & Hamamura, 2007; Yamaguchi et al., 2007). Thus, it is possible that East Asians report lower levels of explicit self-esteem because they are less prone to self-enhancement and instead adopt a more modest self-presentation strategy. A related possibility is that individuals from both cultures engage in self-enhancement biases, but Easterners tend to self-enhance on collectivistic attributes and Westerners tend to self-enhance on individualistic attributes, which are more common on explicit self-esteem scales (Sedikides, Gaertner, & Vevea, 2005). It appears that the structure of the self is not the same as the structure of personality, as embodied in models such as the Five-Factor Model (FFM; John, this volume; McCrae & Costa, this volume). Clearly our self-representations include far more than just beliefs about personality traits, as research using the “Who am I?” test has revealed. The FFM was not intended as a complete model of personality, but rather as a model of individual personality traits. Thus, relational, social, and collective aspects of the self were not included in the research that led to the discovery of the FFM, and most lexical studies of personality structure have explicitly excluded social roles and relationships. Moreover, many aspects of the self do not reflect content domains such as the Big Five but rather how the content of the self is organized, including the degree of differentiation, complexity, and compartmentalization (Donahue et al., 1993; Rafaeli-Mor, Gotlib, & Revelle, 1999; Showers & Kling, 1996; Suh, 2002). Consequently, although the FFM effectively captures the trait-relevant aspects of the personal self, it fails to 15 around the age of two and a half to three years (Lagattuta & Thompson, 2007). Three-year-olds show signs of pride after success on a difficult, but not easy, task, and signs of shame after failing to complete an easy, but not a difficult, task (Lewis, Alessandri, & Sullivan, 1992). Similarly, after failing a task, children as young as 4 show a lack of persistence, view their failure as indicating that they lack the ability to complete the task, and report low expectations for their future performance (Dweck, 1999). These findings suggest that children as young as three or four can make internal attributions about their failures, which requires the presence of a stable self-representational system. Overall, these findings suggest that children have the cognitive skills needed to form specific and stable self-representations around age 4. Does this mean that young children also have a stable evaluation of their overall worth as a person (i.e., global self-esteem)? It is difficult to address this question because young children have obvious verbal limitations and there is no non-verbal test such as the mirror self-recognition task. Instead, the typical approach is to use self-report measures, sometimes aided by pictures or puppets, in which children are asked to report on their beliefs about their general competence and likableness. This research suggests that children as young as four can provide reliable evaluations of themselves, but only when they are evaluating themselves in specific domains (e.g., Marsh, Ellis, & Craven, 2002; Measelle, John, Ablow, Cowan, & Cowan, 2005). It is not until later in childhood, sometime between age 6 and 9, that children can reliably report on their global self-esteem using standard self-report measures, suggesting that younger children lack the cognitive capacity to integrate their domain- specific evaluations into a generalized, global concept of the self (Harter, 2006). We believe this is because global self-esteem requires a representation of the self as a coherent, integrated entity, which may take longer to develop than individual self-representations. However, it is possible 16 that young children have a rudimentary evaluation of the self as generally good or bad. One study found that 5-year old children who talked positively about themselves in a puppet interview had significantly higher scores at age 8 on a traditional self-report measure of self- esteem (Verschueren, Buyck, & Marcoen, 2001). Although a coherent sense of self-worth emerges in childhood, it continues to evolve throughout the lifespan. Individuals who have relatively high (or low) self-esteem at one point in time tend to have high (or low) self-esteem years later, but the stability of self-esteem is relatively low in childhood and far from perfect across the entire lifespan (Trzesniewski, Donnellan, & Robins, 2003). Interestingly, self-esteem and personality show similar levels of stability and follow the same developmental trajectory through much of life: lower stability during childhood and increasingly high stability across adulthood. However, in contrast to personality traits, self-esteem becomes less stable in old age; this developmental shift may be due to greater self-reflection, and thus questioning and reformulation of longstanding self-views, as one approaches the end of life. In addition to examining the stability of individual differences, researchers have also examined whether self-esteem shows aggregate (or mean-level) increases or decreases over time. As we go through life, our self-esteem inevitably waxes and wanes over time, as part of the process of development. These fluctuations in self-esteem reflect changes in our social environment and maturational changes such as puberty and cognitive declines in old age. When these changes are normative, age-dependent, and influence individuals in a similar manner, they will produce aggregate (i.e., population-level) shifts in self-esteem across developmental periods. A number of aggregate changes in self-esteem occur from childhood to old age (see Robins & Trzesniewski, 2005, for a review). On average, young children have relatively high 17 self-esteem, which gradually declines over the course of childhood. Researchers have speculated that children have high self-esteem because it is artificially inflated, and that the subsequent decline reflects an increasing reliance on more realistic information about the self. Self-esteem continues to decline in adolescence, producing a substantial cumulative drop from childhood to adolescence. The adolescent decline has been attributed to physical and neurological changes associated with puberty, cognitive changes associated with the emergence of formal operational thinking, and socio-contextual changes associated with the transition from grade school to junior high school (Harter, 2006). Self-esteem increases gradually throughout adulthood, peaking sometime around the late 60s. Over the course of adulthood, individuals increasingly occupy positions of power and status, which might promote feelings of self-worth. However, self-esteem declines again in old age, beginning around age 70. This decline may be due to the dramatic confluence of changes that occur in old age, including changes in roles (empty nest, retirement), relationships (spousal loss, decreased social support), and physical functioning (declining health, memory loss, reduced mobility). The old age decline may also reflect a shift toward a more modest, humble, and balanced view of the self in old age (Erikson, 1985). That is, as individuals grow old, they may increasingly accept their faults and limitations and become less concerned about inflating their self-worth, which artificially boosts reports of self-esteem earlier in life. Consistent with this interpretation, narcissism also tends to decline with age (Foster, Campbell, & Twenge, 2003). Overall, men and women follow essentially the same developmental trajectory: both genders tend to have high self-esteem in childhood, decline during adolescence, rise gradually throughout adulthood, and then decline in old age. Despite these similarities, there are three important differences. First, there is a small but consistent gender difference across the lifespan, 20 The capacity for self-awareness and self-representations seems to be a universal characteristic of humans. In all human cultures, people have an awareness of their own thoughts and feelings and have relatively stable mental representations of themselves. The universality of these basic aspects of the self is a striking and highly significant fact that is often overlooked in light of the substantial individual and cross-cultural variability that exists in the way the self is manifested. Whenever universal (i.e., species-typical) characteristics are found, scientists generally proceed to comparative, cross-species studies. The self may be part of human nature, but is it unique to humans? Comparative psychologists have shown that a number of other species show advanced forms of self-awareness, including the same three classes of evidence used to evaluate a sense of self in young children: linguistic, cognitive-behavioral, and emotional markers. Linguistic markers. Language-trained great apes (chimps, gorillas, orangutans) show all three linguistic markers (self-referencing, narrative language use, and declarative labeling speech). Koko the gorilla, for example, displayed the capacity for reflexive self-referencing and narrative language use when she signed “me love happy Koko there” after being shown a picture of herself at a birthday party (Patterson & Linden, 1981, p. 86). As Koko’s statement suggests, gorillas might also have personal memories that serve as the basis for some forms of linguistic self-referencing. Monkeys and non-primates do not show any of these linguistic markers. Cognitive-behavioral markers. In a series of seminal studies, Gallup (1970) showed that chimpanzees have the capacity to recognize themselves in a mirror. Gallup allowed chimps to view themselves in a mirror for a few days and then marked their faces with dye while they were anesthetized. Upon subsequently seeing their image in the mirror, the chimps often touched the 21 marks on their face rather than touching the mirror itself. Based on these findings, Gallup (1977) concluded that “Man may not be evolution’s only experiment in self-awareness” (p. 14). In subsequent research, dozens of animal species have been subjected to the mark test, but only chimpanzees (Gallup, 1970), orangutans (Suarez & Gallup, 1981), gorillas (Parker, 1994; Patterson & Cohn, 1994), dolphins (Reiss & Marino, 2001), and Asian elephants (Plotnik, de Waal, Reiss, 2006) have demonstrated the capacity for self-recognition. Interestingly, the first reactions to mirrors by all of these animals are social in nature—smiling, kissing, and vocalizing to their mirror image (Plotnik et al., 2006). Gallup (1977) found that chimpanzees reared in complete isolation from other chimps do not show mirror self-recognition, consistent with Cooley (1902) and Mead’s (1934) theory that the self develops through social interaction and the experience of seeing oneself from the perspective of others. The other two cognitive-behavioral markers—imitation and role-taking—are present in humans by two years of age but extremely rare in other primates. Nonetheless they have been observed in a few cases, suggesting that chimps, orangutans, gorillas, and possibly monkeys have at least some capacity for imitation and role-taking. Emotional markers. Like human children, non-human primates exhibit behaviors that suggest the capacity to experience self-conscious emotions, and related social emotions such as compassion and empathy. Much of this evidence, however, is anecdotal. In one incident, Supinah, an orangutan, was observed attempting the difficult task of hanging a hammock from two trees. After successfully hanging the hammock, Supinah “threw herself back in the hammock” and “hugged herself with both arms” in apparent pride (Hayes, 1951, p. 188). In the primate literature, researchers have described dominant, or alpha male, chimpanzees walking with a “cocky” gait, upright posture, and pilo-erected fur, suggesting the possibility of a 22 precursor to the pride display among these animals (de Waal, 1989). However, more controlled studies are needed. The evidence for empathy in primates is also mostly anecdotal. Non-human primates clearly show helping behaviors. For example, it is not uncommon for a wounded chimp to be attended to—fed, groomed, and protected—by other members of the social group. Dominant adult males even chase away playing infants or noisy group members to keep them from disturbing the injured chimp (Boesch, 1992). A recent series of experiments provides more direct support for empathy and altruism in chimps (Warneken & Tomasello, 2006). After observing an experimenter “drop” an object and act as if she could not reach it, chimps were found to help out by retrieving the object and giving it to the experimenter, suggesting that they understood the experimenter’s dilemma and empathized. However, in tasks where the experimenter’s goal was more difficult to understand (e.g., trying to get around physical obstacles), chimps failed to provide help whereas children as young as 18 months did. Thus, like other aspects of human psychology—personality, memory, attachment—we share many capacities with our phylogenetic cousins, but we differ in the complexity and frequency with which we display these capacities. The findings of cross-species research on the self have several implications. First, they illustrate the value of a comparative perspective in personality psychology (Gosling, Capitanio, & Weinstein, this volume). Comparative research helps identify which aspects of the self are uniquely human and which are common across species. Second, the finding that other species share certain aspects of the human self implies that self-awareness and self-recognition may be evolved capacities. Any capacity that is common to several species of primates is probably not crucially dependent on any species-specific factors, such as culture or language. 25 retrieves, and manipulates information about the world. The computational view of the mind has also spawned the provocative thesis that the self is an illusion – there is no central executive coordinating our thoughts and feelings (Dennett, 2005). Artificial intelligence pioneer Marvin Minsky (1985) describes the mind as a “society of agents”— the agents of the brain are organized hierarchically into nested subroutines with a set of master decision rules. Although it may seem like there is an agent running the “society”, in fact it is just the collective action of neural information processing in multiple parts of the brain. Similarly, some researchers believe that consciousness emerges as different groups of neurons—dealing with vision, memory, or touch—are activated. From this perspective, “there is no seat of consciousness, no internal theater where consciousness is a permanent spectator. Instead, what we experience as consciousness is this constant procession of waxing and waning of neuronal groupings” (Greenfield, 1996, p. 159). Clearly, our current understanding of the neural mechanisms underlying the self is woefully inadequate. If we accept the materialist position and search for the proximate neural mechanisms involved in self processes, we need to go further than grand speculation about a “society of agents” or the “waxing and waning of neuronal groups.” We need to approach the problem of how the brain produces a sense of self using the full array of methods used by cognitive neuroscientists. Below we discuss several neuroscientific methods that have been used to study the self and self-related phenomena. Neuroanatomical studies. An understanding of the gross anatomy of the brain can help us to better understand cross-species comparisons in self processes. For example, what distinguishes the brains of chimps (who show evidence of mirror self-recognition) from the brains of monkeys (who do not)? Which neuroanatomical areas are common to animals that 26 show the capacity for self-recognition, or linguistic self-referencing, or self-conscious emotions? One clue is that humans begin to show evidence of mirror self-recognition around 18 to 24 months of age, which is when the prefrontal cortex begins to mature in structure and function. Although there are likely many reasons why the neuroanatomy of two species might be similar or different, cross-species comparisons can at least identify possible anatomical regions that merit further exploration. Functional neurosurgery and brain lesioning. As with other intrusive techniques, the intentional lesioning of a particular brain region cannot be performed on humans. However, researchers could lesion non-human primates to determine whether damage to a particular area eliminates the capacity for mirror self-recognition and other markers of a sense of self. One kind of brain lesioning that traditionally has been performed on humans is functional neurosurgery. The dramatically altered behavior of lobotomized individuals demonstrates how removing brain tissue can destroy what we normally think of as a person’s self. Another example is split-brain (commisurotomized) patients, whose corpus collosum has been severed, and who consequently suffer a host of deficits related to self processes (Gazzaniga, 1970). Although intentional lesioning of humans is unethical, researchers can now create temporary “lesions” using Transcranial Magnetic Stimulation, which uses a powerful yet noninvasive magnet to alter or suppress activity in specific brain regions. One important advantage of TMS is that it provides a stronger basis for making causal inferences than brain imaging techniques that can only demonstrate correlations with neural activation. To date, we know of only one study that has used this promising method to study self processes; Kwan et al. (2007) showed that TMS stimulation (which serves to suppress activity) of the medial prefrontal 27 cortex reduces the degree to which participants engaged in self-enhancement, defined as perceiving themselves more positively than they perceive others. Neurological disorders and brain damage. Some of the most fascinating avenues for understanding the self have come from the study of neurological patients in whom brain damage has produced cognitive, affective, and behavioral deficits. The complete loss of a sense of self is extremely rare, but many neurological disorders, including autism, Alzheimer’s, Parkinson’s, and epilepsy, produce profound changes in the self (Feinberg & Paul, 2005). There are also a host of neurological disorders characterized by bizarre distortions in body image, including macropsia and micropsia (an Alice in Wonderland like feeling of having either grown incredibly large or incredibly small in size), asomatognosia (e.g., denial that the left side of one’s body is part of one’s self and assertions that any actions by one’s left side were caused by someone else), and exosomesthesia (a pathological extension of the body image in which touches to the self are experienced as touches to nearby physical objects and vice versa.) Sufferers of Lesch-Nyhan syndrome have a pathological tendency toward self-harm, engaging in dramatic self-injurious behaviors such as biting off their fingers and poking their eyes out; they often feel as if their hands and mouth do not belong to them and are under the control of someone or something else, suggesting that their sense of agency – the feeling that “I” am the one controlling my body – is severely distorted. Studies of patients with brain damage due to strokes or accidents suggest that the frontal lobes are involved in self-regulation. Phineas Gage, who had frontal lobe damage after an iron rod penetrated his skull, showed a diminished capacity to self-regulate as well as dramatic personality changes – he became more irreverent, obstinate, and impatient, and less persistent and focused. In general, patients suffering from frontal lobe damage show deficits in the 30 brain correlates of the self provide converging evidence that several regions within the frontal and temporal lobes, including the medial prefrontal cortex (MPFC), dorsolateral prefrontal cortex, orbitofrontal cortex, and anterior cingulate, are more heavily recruited when individuals engage in self-related processes (Beer, 2007). For example, there is now considerable evidence that the MPFC plays a critical role in self-referential processing (Kelley et al., 2002); specifically, activity in this region is associated with encoding information in reference to the self (“Does conscientious describe you?”) but not encoding information in reference to others (“Does conscientious describe George Bush?”) or encoding of general meaning (“Does conscientious have the same meaning as responsible?”). In another study on the neural bases of the self, Inzlicht and Gutsell (2007) used EEG to identify neural correlates of the capacity to control and restrain one’s impulses. Their findings show that after engaging in one act of self-control (trying to control one’s emotions), participants performed worse at a subsequent task requiring self-control and showed decreased activity in a region of the frontal lobes called the anterior cingulate cortex, suggesting that self-regulation depletes rather than strengthens the brain mechanisms that regulate this important aspect of personality. Sharot, Riccardi, Raio, and Phelps (2007) used fMRI to show that enhanced activity in the anterior cingulate cortex and amygdala are associated with optimistic beliefs about the self. Another provocative study showed that activity in the right middle frontal cortex was greater when participants viewed their own rather than familiar faces, and this difference became larger after their “independent selves” were primed by having them read essays containing 1st- person singular pronouns (e.g., I, mine), compared to when their “interdependent selves” were primed by essays containing 2nd-person pronouns (e.g., we, ours) (Sui & Han, 2007). 31 One interesting question emerging from this research is what happens in the brain when participants are not performing any mental tasks, but are simply being self-aware or self- reflecting. It turns out that a set of brain regions in the frontal, parietal, and medial temporal lobes consistently become active when people let their minds wander and engage in self- reflection, mentally traveling back and forth through time to learn from the past and plan for the future (Mason et al., 2007). Neuroscientists refer to this activity as the brain’s “default mode,” suggesting that we spend much of our time exploring past and future selves. Together, these examples illustrate various ways in which the brain can affect self processes, as well as other aspects of personality functioning. The ultimate goal of neuroscience research on the self is to understand how the brain generates self-awareness and self- representations. This goal is complicated because, like other higher-order mental functions, self processes probably emerge out of a complex interplay among multiple brain regions. Moreover, there is a crucial issue of determining the direction of causal relations; for example, does conscious self-reflection cause behavior or is behavior initiated through unconscious brain processes, which the conscious mind then watches and reflects? Finally, the research to date does not conclusively demonstrate that there are any brain states or structures that are distinctively linked to self processes; after reviewing the relevant literature, Gillihan and Farah (2005) concluded that there is little compelling evidence for brain networks devoted to the self that are physically and functionally distinct from those used for more general purpose cognitive processing. At least in principle, new knowledge about the brain can help us refine our theoretical conception of the self and self-related processes. Specifically, the way we conceptualize the self should be consistent with, and constrained by, what we know about how the brain works (e.g., 32 memory researchers used to think that a sense of familiarity was simply a weaker form of recognition memory but research suggests that familiarity and recognition involve distinct brain regions). For example, if one function of the self is to coordinate and regulate inner-body signals and behavioral responses (i.e., self-regulation), then the brain should be doing something different when the self is “in control” than when it is “out of control.” If one motive governing the self system is self-enhancement, then there must be some neural mechanism that “tags” the valence of a self-relevant event and causes positive events to be encoded more deeply than negative ones; similarly, if there is selective retrieval of positive autobiographical memories, then there should be identifiable neural process that enables this to occur (e.g., preferential pathways to representations tagged as positively valenced). Clearly, we have a long way to go before we truly understand the neural mechanisms underlying these and other aspects of the self. However, we believe the new methods of brain science hold a great deal of promise and could ultimately lead to discoveries that provide a foundation for a naturalist view of the self. Is the Self a Product of Evolution? The eminent geneticist Theodosius Dobzhansky (1964) remarked that the self is the chief evolutionary novelty possessed by humans. Consistent with this view, behavioral genetic studies have documented the heritability of self-esteem and other self processes (e.g., Neiss et al., 2005; Neiss et al., 2006). Evidence of heritability supports an evolutionary account of the self, but there are four possible interpretations. First, the self may be “genetic junk;” a characteristic that neither contributes to nor detracts from the organism’s fitness but is nonetheless passed on to succeeding generations. A second possibility is that the self is a functionless by-product of another adaptation, and does not solve any adaptive problems on its own but is carried along 35 Self-regulation. One of the unique aspects of human nature is that we are goal directed, and not just toward proximal goals like grabbing food in front of us but toward long-term goals like succeeding at work, finding a romantic partner, and being a good, moral person. These longterm goals are represented in the self system as various forms of self-representations – ideal selves (“to be a good father”), possible selves (“to be an artist”), dreaded selves (“to become like my mother”), and so on. These goal representations serve as reference points for self-regulation, motivating us to engage in behaviors that move us toward the attainment of desired identities and away from undesired or feared identities; they function as both goals to be pursued and standards against which outcomes are measured. Self-awareness also plays a role in self-regulation, providing a sense of volition that facilitates goal-directed behavior, and allowing for evaluation of goal-relevant outcomes (e.g., awareness of discrepancies between actual and ideal selves). Self-awareness also provides a mechanism for greater flexibility of response in a social environment filled with competing and often conflicting goals. Self-awareness allows us to monitor and regulate not only our overt behavioral responses but also our internal responses (e.g., fear, shame, optimism) to external stimuli and circumstances. Together, the two aspects of the self enable us to prioritize and organize goal-directed behavior, amidst a complex and multiply-nested structure of goals and subgoals. Interestingly, recent research suggests that chimpanzees, our close evolutionary cousins, are also able to engage in fairly complex forms of self-regulation – they use various strategies such as distraction to resist the temptation to eat right away when they know they will get more food later on (Evans & Beran, 2007). Clearly the capacity for self-regulation does not guarantee problem-free and effective pursuit of goals. Humans often engage in self-defeating and maladaptive behaviors. Apparent 36 failures of self-regulation may tell us a great deal about how the self-system functions, as in the case of self-handicapping, where individuals set themselves up for failure in a way that, somewhat paradoxically, protects self-esteem. Information processing filter. In a complex social environment it is inefficient for individuals to attend to and encode all of the information that is constantly bombarding them. The self addresses this dilemma by serving as a filter, or lens, through which the world is experienced. Our self-representations consist of cognitive structures, or schemas, that organize and direct processing of information about the self. Thus, the self serves as a top-down information filter that is guided by four basic motives: accuracy, consistency, popularity (i.e., social status and approval), and positivity. These motives influence which information the self attends to, encodes, retrieves, and acts upon. We have described these motivational orientations in terms of four basic metaphors (Robins & John, 1997). According to the Scientist metaphor, individuals are driven to acquire accurate information about themselves and the world (Bem, 1972; Kelly, 1955; Trope, 1986). Just as the scientist develops empirically based theories, people use facts and observations to develop theories about themselves, engaging in a dispassionate search for accurate self-knowledge. Clearly accurate self-representations can serve an adaptive function, helping us to formulate realistic goals and act in accordance with our actual social status, mate value, and other objectively based self-representations. However, as Pinker (1997) notes, “our brains were shaped for fitness, not for truth” (p. 305); consequently, we sometimes adopt somewhat biased information processing strategies . According to the Consistency Seeker metaphor, individuals strive to see themselves in a consistent manner, confirming their preexisting self-views regardless of reality (Swann, 1997; 37 this volume). In fact, there is considerable evidence that people actively seek out and create contexts in which their self-views will be confirmed, even when these views are inaccurate and/or negative. Similarly, people selectively remember life events that are consistent with current self-representations, reconstructing their past to fit the present (Ross, 1989). A. Although consistency seeking may lead to information processing errors, it can be a useful and efficient heuristic in a highly chaotic social environment. Consistency also serves an interpersonal function, ensuring that people will honor the identities they negotiated in previous social interactions and act similarly over time. According to the Politician metaphor, people strive to present themselves in ways that create the most favorable impressions on others, thereby enhancing their social status and acceptance. This perspective highlights the reciprocal nature of social interaction: social reality is constructed and negotiated through interactions with others, in which behaviors represent public performances that "present images of the self for the social world to see and evaluate" (Schlenker, 1985, p. 21). Like politicians, people target their public performances to different audiences (or constituencies), which place multiple and often conflicting demands and expectations on them. The person-as-politician seeks to "maintain the positive regard of important constituencies to whom he or she feels accountable" (Tetlock, 1992, p. 332), which should increase status, reduce conflict, and facilitate coalition building. Finally, according to the Egotist metaphor, people narcissistically distort information to enhance their self-worth. Virtually every self theory posits some variant of the motive to protect and enhance self-worth, and a large body of research has documented numerous positivity biases in self-perception, including unrealistically positive self-conceptions, self-serving attributions for success and failure, and excessive optimism about the future (Dunning, 2005; Taylor & Brown, 40 failing to do so makes us feel guilty or ashamed of ourselves. Society tells us what kind of person we should be; we internalize these beliefs in the form of actual and ideal self- representations; and self-conscious emotions motivate behavioral action toward the goals embodied in these self-representations. Thus, although we might understand cognitively that working hard is a good thing to do, it sometimes takes the psychological force of emotions like guilt and pride to make us do so. By reinforcing adaptive social behaviors—encouraging us to act in ways that promote social status (getting ahead) and acceptance (getting along)—self- conscious emotions facilitate interpersonal reciprocity, a social arrangement that is highly beneficial in the long term (Trivers, 1971). In summary, self-conscious emotions help us thrive in a social world where attaining status and acceptance is essential to our ability to survive and reproduce. As Kemeny, Gruenwald, and Dickerson (2004) stated, emotions like shame and pride “may be one way that individuals feel their place in the social hierarchy” (p. 154).3 Although self-conscious emotions can be linked to adaptive social behaviors they can also be maladaptive. For example, the tendency to become anxiously preoccupied in social situations and excessively worried about being negatively evaluated can contribute to decreased social competence in the form of shyness. Yet shyness can also be functional when it motivates preparation and rehearsal for important interpersonal events, such as planning ahead for the first day of teaching a new class. Moreover, a moderate amount of wariness regarding strangers and unfamiliar or unpredictable situations undoubtedly had adaptive value in our evolutionary history; Wilson, Coleman, Clark, and Biederman (1993) have argued, based on their research on pumpkin sunfish, that it is adaptive for all species to have a mix of shyness and boldness. The self-conscious emotion of pride also seems to be adaptive in some contexts and maladaptive in others. In the Greek myth, Narcissus ultimately dies from his excessive pride. 41 From an evolutionary perspective, he acted in a particularly maladaptive manner because he spent all of his time gazing at his own reflection and ignored the love of a beautiful nymph with who he could have produced offspring. Research suggests that narcissistic pride, in the form of inflated beliefs about the self, can have short-term adaptive benefits but longterm negative consequences (Robins & Beer, 2001). Moreover, narcissistic individuals are more inclined to cheat on their partners (Hunyady, Josephs, & Jost, 2007), which could lead to lower relationship stability but also to higher numbers of offspring.4 One way to resolve the seeming paradox of pride’s combination of beneficial and detrimental effects is to distinguish between two facets of pride. Several lines of research provide converging support for conceptualizing pride in terms of a “hubristic” or narcissistic facet (defined by terms such as “arrogant” and “conceited”) and an authentic or achievement-based facet (defined by terms such as “confident” and “accomplished”; Tracy & Robins, 2007c). These two facets do not simply reflect good vs. bad, high vs. low arousal, or trait vs. state aspects of pride. Moreover, they are not distinguished by the kinds of events that elicit the pride experience; both occur after success in a range of domains (e.g., academics, romantic relationships). Rather, it is the way in which success is appraised that determines which facet of pride occurs; successes attributed to one’s effort and hard work tend to promote authentic pride, whereas successes attributed to more stable (and less controllable) abilities tend to promote hubristic pride. Authentic and hubristic pride have highly divergent personality correlates. Authentic pride is positively associated with adaptive traits like Extraversion, Agreeableness, Conscientiousness, and genuine self-esteem, whereas hubristic pride is negatively related to these traits but positively associated with self-aggrandizing narcissism, shame-proneness, and 42 aggression. This pattern suggests that authentic pride is the more pro-social, adaptive facet of the emotion (Tracy, Robins, Cheng, & Trzesniewski, in press). The examples of shyness and narcissistic pride illustrate the complexities of the evolutionary perspective—certain aspects of the self may be adaptive in some ways but maladaptive in others. These opposing selection pressures lead to individual differences. Shyness and narcissism may be two ways of approaching the conflict between the dominant social goals of getting along and getting ahead—shy individuals have chosen to focus on getting along and seeking approval whereas narcissistic individuals have focused on getting ahead (Roberts & Robins, 2000). Each may be a viable strategy from an evolutionary perspective. In fact, the two facets of pride may solve unique adaptive problems regarding the acquisition of status. Authentic pride might motivate behaviors geared toward long-term status attainment, whereas hubristic pride may provide a “short-cut” solution, granting status that is more immediate but fleeting, and, in some cases, unwarranted. A related possibility is that the second facet (hubristic pride) evolved as a “cheater” attempt to convince others of one’s success even in the absence of real accomplishments (Tracy & Robins, 2007a). Identity processes. Human social life may be viewed as a series of games—the rules are reflected in cultural norms and the parts that individuals play are defined by their social roles. Winning this game requires that humans form dyadic and group coalitions, and generally navigate within a social structure that, more so than any other species, has complex layers of multiple, overlapping, and sometimes non-transitive social hierarchies (e.g., the highest status hunters were not always the highest status warriors). Imagine living in such a complex social environment without a self—that is, without any stable awareness of your position in the social structure and the roles you play in different contexts and with different interaction partners. 45 that much progress is being made in the field and that a scientific understanding of the self is fundamental to a science of personality. The psychology of the self has an important role to play in the integration of evolutionary biology and neuroscience into personality psychology. The self sits in a privileged position, encompassing and integrating all levels of the person from the biological to the social. This privileged position is fundamentally inclusionary: there is ample room, and indeed serious need, for a variety of approaches to understanding the structure and function of the self, and its relation to other psychological processes. An evolutionary perspective on the self was central to many early theories of personality and social behavior, and it must be considered a central issue for contemporary personality theories. The naturalist agenda outlined by James (1890) remains a worthwhile path for the next century of research on the science of the self. By naturalizing the self, we move the field of personality toward a truly biosocial perspective. 46 References Allport, G.W. (1955). Is the concept of self necessary? Becoming: Basic considerations for a psychology of personality (Chapter 10). New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Allport, G. W. (1960). The open system in personality theory. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 61, 301-310. Baldwin, J. M. (1897). Social and ethical interpretations in mental development. New York: Macmillan. Baron-Cohen, S. (2008). Autism and Asperger’s syndrome (the facts). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Beer, J. S. (2007). Neural systems of self-conscious emotions and their underlying appraisals. In J. L. Tracy, R. W. Robins, & J. P. Tangney (Eds), The self-conscious emotions: Theory and research (pp. 53-67). New York: Guilford. Beer, J. S., John, O. P., Scabini, D., & Knight, R. T. (2006). Orbitofrontal cortex and social behavior: Integrating self-monitoring and emotion-cognition interactions. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 18, 871-879. Beer, J.S., & Lombardo, M. V. (2007). Patient and neuroimaging methodologies in the study of personality and social processes. In R. W. Robins, R.C. Fraley, & R. Krueger (Eds.), Handbook of Research Methods in Personality Psychology. New York: Guilford. Beer, J. S., Shimamura, A. P., & Knight, R. T. (2004). Frontal lobe contributions to executive control of cognitive and social behavior. In M. S. Gazzaniga (Ed.), The Newest Cognitive Neurosciences (3rd Edition) (pp.1091-1104). Cambridge: MIT Press. Bem, D. J. (1972). Self-perception theory. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 6, pp. 1-62). New York: Academic Press. 47 Boesch, C. (1992). New elements of a theory of mind in wild chimpanzees. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 15, 149-150. Brewer, M. B., & Gardner, W. (1996). Who is this "we"? Levels of collective identity and self representations. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 71, 83-93. Brewer, M. B., & Chen, Y. (2007). Where (Who) are collectives in collectivism? Toward conceptual clarification of individualism and collectivism. Psychological Review, 114, 133-151. Brown, J. D. (1998). The self. New York: McGraw-Hill. Byrne, B. M. (1996). Measuring self-concept across the life span: Issues and instrumentation. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Chen & Pickett (in press). The self. Collins, N. L., & Allard, L. M. (2001). Cognitive representations of attachment: the content and function of working models. In G. J. O. Fletcher & M. S. Clark (Eds.), Blackwell Handbook of Social Psychology: Vol. 2. Interpersonal Processes (pp. 60-85). UK: Blackwell. Cooley, C. H. (1902). Human nature and the social order. New York: Scribner’s. Crick, F. H. C. (1994). The astonishing hypothesis: The scientific search for the soul. New York: Scribner's Sons. Damasio, A. R. (2003). Feelings of emotion and the self. In J. Ledoux, J. Debiec, & H. Moss, The self: From soul to brain, Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1001, 253- 261. Decety, J., & Jackson, P. L. (2006). A social-neuroscience perspective on empathy. Psychological Science, 15, 54-58. Dennett, D. C. (2005). Sweet dreams: Philosophical obstacles to a science of consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT press. 50 Harris, P. L. (1992). From simulation to folk psychology: The case for development. Special Issue: Mental simulation: Philosophical and psychological essays. Mind and language, 7, 120-144. Hart, D., & Karmel, M. P. (1996). Self-awareness and self-knowledge in humans, apes, and monkeys. In A. E. Russon, K. A. Bard, S. T. Parker (Eds.), Reaching into thought: The minds of the great apes (p. 325-347). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, England. Harter, S. (2006). The self. In W. Damon & R. M. Lerner (Series Eds.) & N. Eisenberg (Vol. Ed.), Handbook of child psychology: Vol. 3. Social, emotional, and personality development (6th ed., pp. 646-718). New York: Wiley. Hayes, C. (1951). The ape in our house. New York: Harper and Brothers. Heine, S. J., & Hamamura, T. (2007). In search of East Asian self-enhancement. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 11, 4-27. Hilgard, E. R. (1949). Human motives and the concept of the self. American Psychologist, 4, 374-382. Hofstadter, D. R. & Dennett, D. C. (1981). Introduction. The Mind’s I. New York: Bantam. Hunyady, O., Josephs, L., & Jost, J. T. (2007). Priming the primal scene: Betrayal trauma, narcissism, and attitudes toward sexual infidelity. Self and Identity. Inzlicht, M., & Gutsell, J. N. (2007). Running on empty: Neural signals for self- control failure. Psychological Science, 18, 933-937. James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University. Josephs, R. A., Markus, H. R., & Tafarodi, R. W. (1992). Gender and self- esteem. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 63, 391-402. 51 Kagan, J. (1998). Is there a self in infancy? In M. Ferrari and R. J. Sternberg (Eds.), Self- awareness: Its nature and development, (pp. 137-147). New York: Guildford Press. Kanagawa, C., Cross, S. E., & Markus, H. R. (2001). "Who am I?" The cultural psychology of the conceptual self. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 27, 90- 103. Keenan, J. P., Wheeler, M. A., Gallup, G. G., & Pascual-Leone, A. (2000). Self- recognition and the right prefrontal cortex. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4, 338-344. Kelly, G. A. (1955). The psychology of personal constructs. New York: Norton. Kelley, W.M., Macrae, C. N., Wyland, C. L., Caglar, S., Inati, S., & Heatherton, T. F. (2002). Finding the self? An event-related fMRI study. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 14, 785-794. Keltner, D., & Buswell, B. N. (1997). Embarrassment: Its distinct form and appeasement functions. Psychological Bulletin, 122, 250-270. Kemeny, M. E., Gruenewald, T. L., & Dickerson, S. (2004). Shame as the emotional response to threat to the social self: Implications for behavior, physiology, and health. Psychological Inquiry, 15, 153-160. Klein, S. B., Loftus, J., & Kihlstrom, J. F. (1996). Self-knowledge of an amnesic patient: Toward a neuropsychology of personality and social psychology. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 125, 250-260. Klein, S. B., Cosmides, L., Murray, E. R., & Tooby, J. (2004). On the acquisition of knowledge about personality traits: Does learning about the self engage different mechanisms than learning about others? Social Cognition, 22, 367-390. 52 Koch, C. (2004). The quest for consciousness: A neurobiological approach. Woodbury, NY: Roberts and company. Kwan, V. S. Y., Barrios, V., Ganis, G., Gorman, J. Lange, C., Kumar, M., Shepard, A., & Keenan, J. P. (2007). Assessing the neural correlates of self-enhancement bias: a transcranial magnetic stimulation study. Experimental Brain Research, 182, 379-385. Lagattuta, K. H., & Thompson, R. T. (2007). The development of self-conscious emotions: Cognitive processes and social influences. In J. L. Tracy, R. W. Robins, & J. P. Tangney (Eds.), The self-conscious emotions: Theory and research (pp. 91-113). New York: Guilford. Leary, M. R. (2004). What is the self? A plea for clarity. Self and Identity, 3, 1-3. Leary, M. R. (2007). How the self became involved in affective experience: Three sources of self-reflective emotions. In J. L. Tracy, R. W. Robins, & J. P. Tangney (Eds.), The self-conscious emotions: Theory and research (pp. 38-52). New York: Guilford. LeDoux, J. (2003). Synaptic self: How our brains become who we are. New York: Penguin. Levine, B. (2004). Autobiographical memory and the self in time: Brain lesion effects, functional neuroanatomy, and lifespan development. Brain and Cognition, 55, 54-68. Lewis, M., Alessandri, S. M., & Sullivan, M. W. (1992). Differences in shame and pride as a function of children’s gender and task difficulty. Child Development, 63, 630–638. Lockard, J. S., & Paulhus, D. L. (1988). Self-deception: An adaptive mechanism? Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Magno, E., & Allan, K. (2007). Self-reference during explicit memory retrieval: An event-related potential analysis. Psychological Science, 18, 272-277. 55 Plotnik, J. M., de Waal, F. B. M., & Reiss, D. (2006). Self-recognition in an Asian elephant. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 103, 17053-17057. Povinelli, D. J., & Simon, B. B. (1998). Young children’s understanding of briefly versus extremely delayed images of self: Emergence of an autobiographical stance. Developmental Psychology, 34, 188-194. Priel, B., & de Schonen, S. (1986). Self-recognition: A study of a population without mirrors. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 41, 237-250. Ramachandran, V. S. (2004). A brief tour of human consciousness. New York: Pi Press. Ramachandran, V. S. (2007). The neurology of self-awareness [1.8.07]. Edge (www.edge.org). Reiss, D., & Marino, L. (2001). Mirror self-recognition in the bottlenose dolphin: A case of cognitive convergence. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 98, 5937-5942. Robins, R. W., & Beer, J. S. (2001). Positive illusions about the self: Short-term benefits and longterm costs. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 80, 340-352. Robins, R. W., & John, O. P. (1997). The quest for self-insight: Theory and research on accuracy and bias in self-perception. In R. Hogan, J. Johnson, and S. Briggs (Eds.), Handbook of Personality Psychology, (pp. 649-679). New York: Academic Press. Robins, R. W., & Pals, J. L. (2002). Implicit self-theories in the academic domain: Implications for goal orientation, attributions, affect, and self-esteem change. Self and Identity, 1, 313-336. Robins, R. W., Tracy, J. L., & Sherman, J. W. (2007). What makes a personality psychologist? A survey of journal editors and editorial board members. In R. W. Robins, R. C. 56 Fraley, and R. F. Krueger (Eds), Handbook of research methods in personality psychology (pp. 673-678) New York: Guilford. Robins, R. W., & Trzesniewski, K. H. (2005). Self-esteem development across the lifespan. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 14, 158-162. Ross, M. (1989). Relation of implicit theories to the construction of personal histories. Psychological Review, 96, 341-357. Rubin, M., & Hewstone, M. (1998). Social identity theory's self-esteem hypothesis: A review and some suggestions for clarification. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 2, 40- 62. Sapolsky, R. M. (1997). The trouble with testosterone: and other essays on the biology of the human predicament. New York: Scribner. Schimmack, U., Oishi, S., Diener, E. (2005). Individualism: A valid and important dimension of cultural differences between nations. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 9, 17-31. Schlenker, B. R. (1985). Introduction: Foundations of the self in social life. In B. R. Schlenker (Ed.), The self and social life. New York: McGraw-Hill. Schmitt, D. P., & Allik, J. (2005). Simultaneous administration of the Rosenberg Self- Esteem Scale in 53 nations: Exploring the universal and culture-specific features of global self- esteem. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 89, 623-642. Sedikides, C., Gaertner, L., & Vevea, J.L. (2005). Pancultural self-enhancement reloaded. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 89, 539-551. 57 Sedikides, C., & Skowronski, J. J. (2003). Evolution of the symbolic self: Issues and prospects. In M. R. Leary and J. P. Tangney (eds): Handbook of Self and Identity (pp. 594-609). New York, NY: Guilford. Sejnowski, T. (2003). The computational self. In J. Ledoux, J. Debiec, and H. Moss, The self: From soul to brain. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1001, 262-271. Sharot, T., Riccardi, A. M., Raio, C. M., & Phelps, E. A. (2007). Neural mechanisms mediating optimism bias. Nature, 450, 102-105. Showers, C. J., & Kling, K. C. (1996). The organization of self-knowledge: Implications for mood regulation. In L. L. Martin & A. Tesser (Eds.), Striving and feeling: Interactions among goals, affect, and self-regulation (pp. 151-173). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Skinner, B. F. (1990). Can psychology be a science of the mind? American Psychologist, 45, 1206-1210. Spencer-Rodgers, J., Peng, K., Wang, L., & Hou, Y. (2004). Dialectical self-esteem and east-west differences in psychological well-being. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 30, 1416-1432. Suarez, S. D., & Gallup, G. G. (1981). Self-recognition in chimpanzees and organutans, but not gorillas. Journal of Human Evolution, 10, 175-188. Suh, E. M. (2002). Culture, identity consistency, and subjective well-being. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 83, 1378–1391. Sui, J., & Han, S. (2007). Self-construal priming modulates neural substrates of self- awareness. Psychological Science, 18, 861–866. Sutin, A. R., & Robins, R. W. (2005). Continuity and correlates of emotions and motives in self-defining memories. Journal of Personality, 73, 793-824. 60 Turner, J. C., & Onorato, R. S. (1999). Social identity, personality, and the self-concept: A self-categorization perspective. In T. R. Tyler, R. M. Kramer, & O. P. John (Eds.), The psychology of the social self (pp. 11-46). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Tyler, T. R., Kramer, R. M., & John, O. P. (Eds.) (1999). The psychology of the social self. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Verschueren, K., Buyck, P., & Marcoen, A. (2001). Self-representations and socioemotional competence in young children: A 3-year longitudinal study. Developmental Psychology, 37, 126-134. Wang, Q. (2006). Culture and the development of self-knowledge. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 15, 182-187. Warneken, F., & Tomasello, M. (2006). Altruistic helping in human infants and young chimpanzees. Science, 1301-1303. Williams, G. C. (1966). Adaptation and natural selection: A critique of some current evolutionary thought. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Wilson, D. S., Coleman, K., Clark, A. B., & Biederman, L. (1993). Shy-bold continuum in pumpkinseed sunfish (Lepomis gibbosus ): An ecological study of a psychological trait. Journal of Comparative Psychology, 107, 250-260. Yamaguchi, S., Greenwald, A. G., Banaji, M. R., Murakami, F., Chen, D., Shiomura, K., Kobayashi, C., Cai, H., & Krendl, A. (2007). Apparent universality of positive implicit self- esteem. Psychological Science, 18, 498-500. 50% 45% 40% 35% 30% 25% 20% 15% 10% Figure 1: % of Articles in JPSP with “Self” as a Keyword 61 62 Figure 2: Two Classes of Self Phenomena “I” Self as subject Self as perceiver Sentience Qualia Phenomenology Subjective experience Agent/homunculus Self-awareness Self-consciousness “Me” Self as object Self as perceived Personal (episodic) memories Self-knowledge (semantic memory) Linguistic/symbolic self Self-concept Self-representation Self-theories Ideal/ought/possible selves Ongoing Sense of Self-Awareness Stable Self- Representations
Docsity logo



Copyright © 2024 Ladybird Srl - Via Leonardo da Vinci 16, 10126, Torino, Italy - VAT 10816460017 - All rights reserved